In This Article Expand or collapse the "in this article" section Dialectic in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy

  • Introduction
  • General Overviews and Collections
  • Dialectic before Socrates
  • The “Dialectical” School
  • Academic Skeptics

Classics Dialectic in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
by
Alexander Bown
  • LAST REVIEWED: 12 January 2023
  • LAST MODIFIED: 12 January 2023
  • DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195389661-0389

Introduction

What is dialectic? The question has no simple answer: different philosophers and philosophical schools in the ancient world use the expression “dialectic” (or rather the Greek “dialektikē”) in a number of importantly different ways. But there is at least some family resemblance between the various methods, disciplines, activities, and forms of argument that bear the name. The word is cognate with the ordinary Greek verb “dialegesthai,” which can mean “to have a conversation,” “to discuss,” or “to argue” (inter alia). Accordingly, the earliest uses of “dialectic” refer to practices that involve discussing some topic by means of questions and answers; later uses typically retain some connection to the idea of a dialogue, although this connection is sometimes tenuous. Some of the principal accounts covered in this article are as follows: first, Plato uses the expression “dialectic” (which he may have coined) for various methods of philosophical inquiry into principles, forms, or definitions. These methods range from Socrates’ practice of conducting a conversation by asking a series of questions that gradually uncover inconsistencies in his interlocutor’s beliefs, to more abstract procedures of somehow grasping fundamental, explanatory principles and deriving further truths from them. Second, Aristotle regards dialectic as the skill of being able to discuss any question whatever on the basis of common-sense or widely accepted opinions. Its role in philosophical inquiry is less central for him than for Plato, but some scholars think that he still takes it to have an important part to play in investigations into fundamental principles. Third, a group of philosophers associated with Diodorus Cronus may have belonged to a so-called “Dialectical School.” These philosophers have a great deal of interest in logical paradoxes and develop influential views on the truth conditions of conditionals and on modality. Fourth, Stoic philosophers class dialectic as a part of logic, one of the three main branches of philosophy. Various accounts are recorded: according to one, it is the skill of being able to conduct oneself well in question-and-answer discussion; according to another, it is “the science of what is true, what is false, and what is neither” (DL 7.62). Finally, some skeptical philosophers of the Hellenistic period engage in practices that have often been called dialectical. Arcesilaus and Carneades, two leaders of Plato’s Academy during its skeptical phase, were known for their ability to argue on both sides of any given question, with the aim of inducing suspension of judgement.

General Overviews and Collections

The introduction of Fink 2012 provides a useful account of how dialectical exchanges may have worked in practice. The introductions of Gourinat and Lemaire 2016 and Bénatouïl and Ierodiakonou 2018 provide general overviews of the varying practices, disciplines, and subject matters known as “dialectic” by ancient philosophers. The essays covered by these collections are of a high quality and collectively fairly comprehensive in their coverage; many are referred to in later sections of this article. Finally, Sichirollo 1966 examines the use of the Greek “dialektikē” and cognate expressions in non-philosophical as well as philosophical writing.

  • Bénatouïl, T., and K. Ierodiakonou, eds. 2018. Dialectic after Plato and Aristotle. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    The proceedings of the thirteenth Symposium Hellenisticum. Contributors discuss various treatments of dialectic in the Hellenistic and Imperial periods. A wide range of philosophers is considered, including Megarians, early Peripatetics, Epicureans, Stoics, Academic Skeptics, Pyrrhonists, and Galen.

  • Fink, J. L., ed. 2012. The development of dialectic from Plato to Aristotle. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Collection of essays on dialectic in Plato and Aristotle. Contributions attend not only to the ways in which these philosophers theorize about dialectic, but also to questions concerning dialectic in practice.

  • Gourinat, J.-B., and J. Lemaire, eds. 2016. Logique et dialectique dans l’Antiquité. Paris: Vrin.

    Wide-ranging collection of essays on ancient logic and dialectic. Most essays are written in French; some are in English. Philosophers and philosophical schools covered include Plato, Aristotle, some Hellenistic schools, and some Neoplatonists.

  • Sichirollo, L. 1966. Διαλέγεσθαι-Dialektik: Von Homer bis Aristoteles. Hildesheim, Germany: Georg Olms Verlag.

    Monograph examining the use of the expression “dialectic” (“dialektikē”) and associated vocabulary by a range of Greek authors, including both philosophers and non-philosophers.

back to top

Users without a subscription are not able to see the full content on this page. Please subscribe or login.

How to Subscribe

Oxford Bibliographies Online is available by subscription and perpetual access to institutions. For more information or to contact an Oxford Sales Representative click here.

Article

Up

Down