Normativity and Social Explanation
- LAST REVIEWED: 02 December 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 25 June 2013
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0235
- LAST REVIEWED: 02 December 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 25 June 2013
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0235
Introduction
Normativity is what gives reasons their force, makes words meaningful, and makes rules and laws binding. Onora O’Neill, in her introduction to Christine Korsgaard’s influential The Sources of Normativity (1996), says “normativity is everywhere.” Normativity is present whenever correctness is present. What normativity is taken to inhere in varies, but in general the normative is taken to be a class of facts, or a class of things accepted to be true, valid, or otherwise indispensable to thought or science. Defenders of such claims argue that normative facts are not empirical facts, not reducible to empirical facts, and, crucially, cannot be explained away by ordinary “scientific” or naturalistic explanations. This bibliography is concerned with a subset of the problem: the cases in which explanations of normativity compete with cognitive science and social science explanations of human behavior, intentions, actions, and linguistic practices. The candidates up for explanation in the cognitive and social sciences vary, depending on the philosopher in question. The usual candidates are often such things as rationality, practical reason, modal logic, concepts, inferential relations, correct linguistic usage, rule following, and ethical norms or behavior. A model form of the distinction is this: predicting that I will arrive at work at nine o’clock tomorrow is different from promising that I will, and promising cannot be reduced to prediction or mere expectation; rather, it creates or invokes a sui generis normative relation, binding or committing the speaker, which allows the speaker to be held accountable by others. Yet normativists, the philosophers committed to this idea, admit that the idea of a noncausal normative realm and a body of normative objects is spooky (McDowell 1994 cited under General Overviews), and they are reluctant to embrace a metaphysics that is sharply at odds with broadly naturalistic explanations. This tension is the source of the problem of naturalism and normativity. Is it possible to account “naturalistically” for the normative by explanations that are part of the normal stream of cognitive science or social scientific explanation? Put simply, it is one dimension to the question of whether science, in some sense, can explain everything that needs explaining. Normativists claim that there are essential things that science in the narrow sense cannot explain. But in order to avoid dualism, they often argue for a liberal naturalism that allows for some kind of normativity.
General Overviews
Although initially philosophers interested in offering normative explanations usually focused on one specific topic (e.g., rule-following considerations in the philosophy of language), a number of contemporary texts address a variety of topics surrounding normative and social explanation from a holistic perspective. That is, some philosophers have attempted to offer broad accounts of normativity that encompass a number of topics (usually the mental, perception, language, persons, and action) in an effort to offer a unified and interrelated explanation for all topics under consideration. Thus one finds in Brandom 1994 and Wedgewood 2007 an attempt to offer an explanation that, if correct, would necessarily entail a normative understanding of the mind, language, and persons. McDowell 1994 and McDowell 1998 offers a slightly more focused account of normativity than Brandom 1994 or Wedgewood 2007. Nonetheless, McDowell’s texts do attempt to convey the purportedly interconnected nature of the mind, meta-ethics, perception, and language. Other holistic accounts, such as Millar 2004 and Knowles 2003, address a variety of philosophical topics that confront anyone interested in defending normative explanations. Owens 2000 is of particular interest as he attempts to connect issues in meta-ethics, metaphysics, and epistemology in order to shine new light on debates between internalists and externalists in epistemology. Yet not all holistic accounts of normativity defend normative explanations. Turner 2010 offers a broad critique of normative accounts that covers issues in the philosophy of language, mind, and law. Machery 2009 examines the conflicts between philosophical accounts of concepts and psychological and cognitive science accounts. Although most of these accounts address a number of different topics and traditions; what unifies their approach to understanding normativity is their interest in offering a broadly holistic, normative explanation of a variety of topics.
Brandom, Robert. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994.
Brandom’s text focuses on offering a broadly normativist and expressivist conception of persons and the mental. Specifically, chapters 1–4, 8, and 9 address issues surrounding norms and action, perception, meaning, mental representation, and social practices, among other topics.
Knowles, Jonathan. Norms, Naturalism, and Epistemology: The Case for Science without Norms. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.
Although Knowles claims to focus on epistemology, broadly construed, the bulk of the text acts as an advanced source for arguments over the relationship between unflinchingly naturalist accounts and thoroughly normativists approaches to epistemology and science; this is mainly for those interested in the clash between naturalized and “non-naturalized” epistemology. Despite the title of this book, see Owens 2000 for a more epistemologically centered account of normativity.
Machery, Eduard. Doing without Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195306880.001.0001
One of the essential moves in normativism is the claim that the indispensable “concept” of concept is itself “normative.” Machery systematically reviews the various psychological theories of concepts, together with the supporting empirical evidence, to show how poorly the philosophical approach matches the evidence and raises the question of what is indispensable for cognition.
McDowell, John. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994.
This now-classic work addresses a number of issues surrounding perceptual knowledge, mental content, and the relationship between the natural and the normative. In McDowell’s account issues surrounding normativity are exhibited in his discussion of conceptual and nonconceptual content as well as the induction of individuals into the “space of reasons.”
McDowell, John. Meaning, Knowledge, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.
This collection of McDowell’s previously published essays contains a number of entries that touch on normative concerns. More specifically, the relevant essays focus on standards of correctness in relation to meaning and mental content. McDowell 1994 is a better starting point for the unacquainted.
Millar, Alan. Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199254408.001.0001
Millar’s text offers a broad account of the issues facing those that defend normative explanations of persons. This constitutes an “overlooked gem” in the debates over normative explanation and is a great starting point for the unfamiliar.
O’Neil, Onora. “Introduction.” In The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora O’Neil, xi–xv. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Oneil’s introduction to The Sources of Normativity offers a broad account of the role of normativity in Korsgaard’s philosophy and touches on general issues surrounding normative accounts of human action. See the introduction in Millar 2004 for a more detailed exposition of similar issues.
Owens, David. Reason without Freedom: The Problem of Epistemic Normativity. New York: Routledge, 2000.
Owens’s work creates a middle ground between internalist and externalist concerns about knowledge and presents an expansive analysis of the necessary views of freedom and responsibility that are a consequence of his view (as well as those presupposed by externalism and internalism).
Turner, Stephen. Explaining the Normative. Cambridge, UK: Polity, 2010.
Turner examines the influential kinds of circular, transcendental, and tu quoque arguments for normativism and contrasts these arguments to standard social science explanations, showing that normativism relies on dubious social theory. See the Oxford Bibliographies article on Normativity and Social Explanation. Turner 2010 is a good counterbalance to the rest of this section.
Wedgewood, Ralph. The Nature of the Normative. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251315.001.0001
Wedgewood’s main argument rests heavily on the idea that normative claims are strongly supervenient on factual claims. The normativity of the intentional is one example: intentional claims are strongly supervenient on facts about the world in the sense that for an intention to change something in the non-intentional world must also change. But the facts in the nonintentional world do nothing to warrant the kinds of considerations that are inferentially linked to intention, such as the possession of the concepts relevant to having the intention.
Users without a subscription are not able to see the full content on this page. Please subscribe or login.
How to Subscribe
Oxford Bibliographies Online is available by subscription and perpetual access to institutions. For more information or to contact an Oxford Sales Representative click here.
Article
- A Priori Knowledge
- Abduction and Explanatory Reasoning
- Ability
- Abortion
- Abstract Objects
- Action
- Addams, Jane
- Adorno, Theodor
- Aesthetic Hedonism
- Aesthetics, Analytic Approaches to
- Aesthetics, Continental
- Aesthetics, Environmental
- Aesthetics, History of
- African Philosophy, Contemporary
- Alexander, Samuel
- Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
- Anarchism, Philosophical
- Animal Rights
- Anscombe, G. E. M.
- Anthropic Principle, The
- Anti-Natalism
- Applied Ethics
- Aquinas, Thomas
- Argument Mapping
- Art and Emotion
- Art and Knowledge
- Art and Morality
- Artifacts
- Assertion
- Astell, Mary
- Atheism
- Augustine
- Aurelius, Marcus
- Austin, J. L.
- Autonomy
- Bacon, Francis
- Bayesianism
- Beauty
- Belief
- Bergson, Henri
- Berkeley, George
- Biology, Philosophy of
- Bolzano, Bernard
- Boredom, Philosophy of
- British Idealism
- Buber, Martin
- Buddhist Philosophy
- Burge, Tyler
- Business Ethics
- Camus, Albert
- Canterbury, Anselm of
- Carnap, Rudolf
- Causation
- Cavendish, Margaret
- Certainty
- Chemistry, Philosophy of
- Childhood, Philosophy of
- Chinese Philosophy
- Cognitive Ability
- Cognitive Phenomenology
- Cognitive Science, Philosophy of
- Coherentism
- Color
- Communitarianism
- Computational Science
- Computer Science, Philosophy of
- Computer Simulations
- Comte, Auguste
- Concepts
- Conceptual Role Semantics
- Conditionals
- Confirmation
- Confucius
- Connectionism
- Consciousness
- Constructive Empiricism
- Contemporary Hylomorphism
- Contextualism
- Contrastivism
- Cook Wilson, John
- Cosmology, Philosophy of
- Critical Theory
- Culture and Cognition
- Daoism and Philosophy
- Davidson, Donald
- de Beauvoir, Simone
- de Montaigne, Michel
- Death
- Decision Theory
- Deleuze, Gilles
- Democracy
- Depiction
- Derrida, Jacques
- Descartes, René
- Descartes, René: Sensory Representations
- Descriptions
- Dewey, John
- Dialetheism
- Disability
- Disagreement, Epistemology of
- Disjunctivism
- Dispositions
- Divine Command Theory
- Doing and Allowing
- du Châtelet, Emilie
- Dummett, Michael
- Dutch Book Arguments
- Early Modern Philosophy, 1600-1750
- Eastern Orthodox Philosophical Thought
- Education, Philosophy of
- Emotion
- Engineering, Philosophy and Ethics of
- Environmental Philosophy
- Epicurus
- Epistemic Basing Relation
- Epistemic Defeat
- Epistemic Injustice
- Epistemic Justification
- Epistemic Philosophy of Logic
- Epistemology
- Epistemology and Active Externalism
- Epistemology, Bayesian
- Epistemology, Feminist
- Epistemology, Internalism and Externalism in
- Epistemology, Moral
- Epistemology of Education
- Ethical Consequentialism
- Ethical Deontology
- Ethical Intuitionism
- Eugenics and Philosophy
- Events, The Philosophy of
- Evidence
- Evidence-Based Medicine, Philosophy of
- Evidential Support Relation In Epistemology, The
- Evil
- Evolutionary Debunking Arguments in Ethics
- Evolutionary Epistemology
- Experimental Philosophy
- Explanations of Religion
- Extended Mind Thesis, The
- Externalism and Internalism in the Philosophy of Mind
- Faith, Conceptions of
- Fatalism
- Feminist Aesthetics and Feminist Philosophy of Art
- Feminist Philosophy
- Feyerabend, Paul
- Fichte, Johann Gottlieb
- Fiction
- Fictionalism
- Fictionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Film, Philosophy of
- Foot, Philippa
- Foreknowledge
- Forgiveness
- Formal Epistemology
- Foucault, Michel
- Free Will
- Frege, Gottlob
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg
- Generics
- Geometry, Epistemology of
- God and Possible Worlds
- God, Arguments for the Existence of
- God, The Existence and Attributes of
- Grice, Paul
- Habermas, Jürgen
- Hart, H. L. A.
- Heaven and Hell
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Aesthetics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Metaphysics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of History
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of Politics
- Heidegger, Martin: Early Works
- Hermeneutics
- Higher Education, Philosophy of
- History, Philosophy of
- Hobbes, Thomas
- Horkheimer, Max
- Human Rights
- Hume, David: Aesthetics
- Hume, David: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Husserl, Edmund
- Idealizations in Science
- Identity in Physics
- Images
- Imagination
- Imagination and Belief
- Immanuel Kant: Political and Legal Philosophy
- Impossible Worlds
- Incommensurability in Science
- Indian Philosophy
- Indispensability of Mathematics
- Inductive Reasoning
- Infinitism
- Instruments in Science
- Intellectual Humility
- Intentionality, Collective
- Intuitions
- James, William
- Japanese Philosophy
- Kant and the Laws of Nature
- Kant, Immanuel: Aesthetics and Teleology
- Kant, Immanuel: Ethics
- Kant, Immanuel: Theoretical Philosophy
- Kierkegaard, Søren
- Knowledge
- Knowledge-first Epistemology
- Knowledge-How
- Kristeva, Julia
- Kuhn, Thomas S.
- Lacan, Jacques
- Lakatos, Imre
- Langer, Susanne
- Language of Thought
- Language, Philosophy of
- Latin American Philosophy
- Laws of Nature
- Legal Epistemology
- Legal Philosophy
- Legal Positivism
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm
- Levinas, Emmanuel
- Lewis, C. I.
- Liberty
- Literature, Philosophy of
- Locke, John
- Locke, John: Identity, Persons, and Personal Identity
- Logic
- Lottery and Preface Paradoxes, The
- Lucretius
- Machiavelli, Niccolò
- Martin Heidegger: Later Works
- Martin Heidegger: Middle Works
- Marx, Karl
- Material Constitution
- Mathematical Explanation
- Mathematical Pluralism
- Mathematical Structuralism
- Mathematics, Ontology of
- Mathematics, Philosophy of
- Mathematics, Visual Thinking in
- McDowell, John
- McTaggart, John
- Meaning of Life, The
- Mechanisms in Science
- Medically Assisted Dying
- Medicine, Contemporary Philosophy of
- Medieval Logic
- Medieval Philosophy
- Memory
- Mental Causation
- Mereology
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice
- Meta-epistemological Skepticism
- Metaepistemology
- Metaethics
- Metametaphysics
- Metaphilosophy
- Metaphor
- Metaphysical Grounding
- Metaphysics, Contemporary
- Metaphysics, Feminist
- Midgley, Mary
- Mill, John Stuart
- Mind, Metaphysics of
- Modal Epistemology
- Modality
- Models and Theories in Science
- Modularity
- Montesquieu
- Moore, G. E.
- Moral Contractualism
- Moral Naturalism and Nonnaturalism
- Moral Responsibility
- Multiculturalism
- Murdoch, Iris
- Music, Analytic Philosophy of
- Nationalism
- Natural Kinds
- Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Naïve Realism
- Neo-Confucianism
- Neuroscience, Philosophy of
- Nietzsche, Friedrich
- Nonexistent Objects
- Normative Ethics
- Normative Foundations, Philosophy of Law:
- Normativity and Social Explanation
- Objectivity
- Occasionalism
- Olfaction
- Ontological Dependence
- Ontology of Art
- Ordinary Objects
- Other Minds
- Pacifism
- Pain
- Panpsychism
- Paradoxes
- Particularism in Ethics
- Pascal, Blaise
- Paternalism
- Patriotism
- Peirce, Charles Sanders
- Perception, Cognition, Action
- Perception, The Problem of
- Perfectionism
- Persistence
- Personal Identity
- Phenomenal Concepts
- Phenomenal Conservatism
- Phenomenology
- Philosophy for Children
- Photography, Analytic Philosophy of
- Physicalism
- Physicalism and Metaphysical Naturalism
- Physics, Experiments in
- Plato
- Plotinus
- Political Epistemology
- Political Obligation
- Political Philosophy
- Popper, Karl
- Pornography and Objectification, Analytic Approaches to
- Practical Knowledge
- Practical Moral Skepticism
- Practical Reason
- Pragmatics
- Pragmatism
- Probabilistic Representations of Belief
- Probability, Interpretations of
- Problem of Divine Hiddenness, The
- Problem of Evil, The
- Propositions
- Psychology, Philosophy of
- Punishment
- Pyrrhonism
- Qualia
- Quietism
- Quine, W. V. O.
- Race
- Racist Jokes
- Rationalism
- Rationality
- Rawls, John: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Realism and Anti-Realism
- Realization
- Reasons in Epistemology
- Reductionism in Biology
- Reference, Theory of
- Reid, Thomas
- Relativism
- Reliabilism
- Religion, Philosophy of
- Religious Belief, Epistemology of
- Religious Experience
- Religious Pluralism
- Ricoeur, Paul
- Rights
- Risk, Philosophy of
- Rorty, Richard
- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques
- Rule-Following
- Russell, Bertrand
- Ryle, Gilbert
- Sartre, Jean-Paul
- Schopenhauer, Arthur
- Science and Religion
- Science, Theoretical Virtues in
- Scientific Explanation
- Scientific Progress
- Scientific Realism
- Scientific Representation
- Scientific Revolutions
- Scotus, Duns
- Self-Knowledge
- Sellars, Wilfrid
- Semantic Externalism
- Semantic Minimalism
- Semiotics
- Seneca
- Senses, The
- Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology
- Shepherd, Mary
- Singular Thought
- Situated Cognition
- Situationism and Virtue Theory
- Skepticism, Contemporary
- Skepticism, History of
- Slurs, Pejoratives, and Hate Speech
- Smith, Adam: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge
- Social Epistemology
- Social Identity
- Sounds and Auditory Perception
- Space and Time
- Speech Acts
- Spinoza, Baruch
- Stebbing, Susan
- Strawson, P. F.
- Structural Realism
- Suicide
- Supererogation
- Supervenience
- Tarski, Alfred
- Technology, Philosophy of
- Testimony, Epistemology of
- Theoretical Terms in Science
- Thomas Aquinas' Philosophy of Religion
- Thought Experiments
- Time and Tense
- Time Travel
- Toleration
- Torture
- Transcendental Arguments
- Tropes
- Trust
- Truth
- Truth and the Aim of Belief
- Truthmaking
- Turing Test
- Two-Dimensional Semantics
- Understanding
- Uniqueness and Permissiveness in Epistemology
- Utilitarianism
- Vagueness
- Value of Knowledge
- Vienna Circle
- Virtue Epistemology
- Virtue Ethics
- Virtues, Epistemic
- Virtues, Intellectual
- Voluntarism, Doxastic
- War
- Weakness of Will
- Weil, Simone
- Well-Being
- William of Ockham
- Williams, Bernard
- Wisdom
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Early Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Later Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Middle Works
- Wollstonecraft, Mary