Philosophy Immanuel Kant: Ethics
by
Lara Denis
  • LAST REVIEWED: 10 November 2022
  • LAST MODIFIED: 30 September 2013
  • DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0225

Introduction

The ethical theory of Immanuel Kant (b. 1724–d. 1804) exerted a powerful influence on the subsequent history of philosophy and continues to be a dominant approach to ethics, rivaling consequentialism and virtue ethics. Kant’s ethical thought continues to be studied in itself, as a part of his critical system of philosophy, in its historical context, and in relation to particular practical questions. Kant’s writings and lectures display the influence of the Stoics, Rousseau, Crusius, Wolff, Hutcheson, Hume, and others; Fichte, Hegel, Nietzsche, Bradley, Greene, Habermas, and Rawls are among the many philosophers whose moral philosophies can be read (in part) as responses to Kant. Salient foundational features of Kant’s ethics include: its a priori method, its conception of the will as autonomous, its categorical imperative, its theory of freedom, and its account of moral motivation. Kant maintained that foundational moral principles must be a priori, not based on observation or experience. Kant takes the moral law to be legislated by the will to itself. Unlike holy beings, human beings experience morality as a constraint upon our wills. For us, the moral law is a categorical imperative. All ethical duties are ultimately grounded in this supreme moral principle. If we are bound to obey the moral law, we must be capable of doing so; Kant holds that, even assuming causal determinism in the phenomenal world, morality reveals our (noumenal) freedom to us. Kant attributes moral worth only to action done from duty (i.e., from respect for the law), not from inclination. Significant aspects of Kant’s fully developed ethical theory include its rich theory of virtue and the virtues, its taxonomy of duties (which include duties to oneself as well as to others), its distinctive conceptions of the highest good and human evil, and its connections with Kant’s philosophies of history, religion, and human nature. Many of Kant’s own discussions of particular duties, virtues, and vices are controversial. For example, Kant appears to condemn all lies as violations of a duty to oneself. This entry focuses on Kant’s ethics rather than Kantian ethics more broadly. Despite that, it includes a number of pieces that apply, extend, or revise Kant’s ethics in some ways, as well as interpretations of Kant’s ethics that some commentators may object stray too far from Kant’s own stated views. Kant’s political philosophy is discussed only peripherally here, save for the section on the Doctrine of Right of the Metaphysics of Morals.

General Overviews

Readers who wish to understand Kant’s ethics within the context of his philosophy as a whole will find Guyer 2006 an illuminating introduction. Several chapters are devoted to Kant’s moral and political philosophy, as well as to aspects of Kant’s philosophy of religion, history, and nature that bear on his ethics. The book is accessible enough for advanced undergraduates and other readers new to Kant. Other selections suitable for those new to Kant are Johnson 2012, Schneewind 1992, and Uleman 2010. Uleman 2010 is the most comprehensive and detailed, and written with advanced undergraduates in mind. Like Guyer 2006, Uleman 2010 can serve as a textbook. Johnson 2012 is available online and periodically updated. It provides an overview that focuses on the foundational doctrines of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, though it is not limited to them. Schneewind 1992 is particularly informative with respect to Kant’s influences and intellectual context and development. The remaining four selections are highly influential books. Paton 1947 is especially worth reading on the categorical imperative and its formulations. O'Neill 1975 is especially important when it comes to topics of maxim formulation and the contradiction tests of the first formulation of the categorical imperative. Allison 1990 is particularly valuable for the discussion of freedom. Wood 1999 is the most wide ranging and the most interested in drawing on Kant’s work in practical anthropology.

  • Allison, Henry. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139172295Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Highly influential treatment of Kant’s moral theory, treating topics ranging from freedom, reason, and will, to virtue, character, and evil.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. Kant. New York: Routledge, 2006.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Accessible enough for undergraduates, but sufficiently distinctive in its interpretations as to be of interest to more advanced readers. Brings Kant’s philosophies of nature, history, and religion to bear on his ethics; discusses Kant’s philosophy of right in addition to his theory of virtue. Overview of Kant’s entire philosophical system.

    Find this resource:

  • Johnson, Robert. “Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2012.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A brief, clear, and accessible introduction to Kant’s ethics, focused on Kant’s foundational positions on the nature of moral philosophy, the categorical imperative and its formulations, the good will and moral motivation, and autonomy. Includes bibliography and links to other Internet resources, including but not limited to related Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entries. Updated every few years.

    Find this resource:

  • O'Neill, Onora. Acting on Principle: An Essay in Kantian Ethics. New York: Columbia University Press, 1975.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A highly influential work on Kant’s ethics. Much attention is focused on the formula of universal law, its contradiction tests, and related issues regarding ends, maxims, and intentions. Other topics include Kant’s taxonomy of duties, moral worth, supererogation, and conflicts of duty. Concise and systematic.

    Find this resource:

  • Paton, H. J. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. London: Hutchinson’s University Library, 1947.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Focuses on such foundational topics as the critical method, the good will, duty, reverence for the law, the intelligible world, and freedom—and especially the categorical imperative. Its influence on English-language Kant scholarship would be difficult to overstate.

    Find this resource:

  • Schneewind, J. B. “Autonomy, Obligation, and Virtue: An Overview of Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant. Edited by Paul Guyer, 309–341. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

    DOI: 10.1017/CCOL0521365872Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A philosophically and historically informative introduction. Sets Kant’s moral philosophy in the contexts of Kant’s broader philosophy and its development. Also situates Kant’s moral philosophy in relation to significant influences as Wolff, Crusius, Rousseau, and Hutcheson.

    Find this resource:

  • Uleman, Jennifer K. An Introduction to Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511801082Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Geared toward advanced undergraduates, graduate students, and above. A sophisticated introduction to Kant’s moral theory. Main topics include practical reason; will, choice, and desire; freedom and its place in nature; the categorical imperative; and the goodness of a good will.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173254Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Five chapters concern the “metaphysical foundations” of Kant’s ethics; the focus here falls on the categorical imperative, its formulations, and their applications. The focus of the other four main chapters is the relation of morality to human nature. Topics here include practical anthropology, history, inclinations and passions, and radical evil.

    Find this resource:

Reference Works

With so much written by Kant, a lexicon can be a valuable research aid. Eisler 1994 is a venerable Kant-lexicon; it is in German. Some entries are just a few lines long; others, such as those referring to terms for key concepts in Kant’s philosophy, stretch for many pages. The other two resources are in English. Johnson 2012 provides an overview of Kant’s ethics. It is updated periodically and has a helpful bibliography and set of links to other Internet resources. Kant in the Classroom is a resource specific to Kant’s lectures—in all areas, not only ethics. This is an extremely valuable aid, since Kant gave so many lectures and there are so many sets of student notes. It is periodically updated. It is a rich resource for the scholar (or aspiring scholar). All these reference works can be accessed via the web; Kant in the Classroom and Johnson 2012 are only accessible this way.

  • Eisler, Rudolf. Kant-Lexicon: Nachschlagewerk zu Kants sämtlichen Schriften, Briefen und handschriftlichm Nachlaß. Hildesheim, Germany: Olms, 1994.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A–Z guide of terms Kant uses with explanations of them and their relations to other terms, often quoted from Kant’s writings, with citations to the relevant passages. Reprint of 1930 edition, published in Berlin by Akademie Verlag. This work is also available online. In German.

    Find this resource:

  • Johnson, Robert. “Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2012.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Clear, accessible introduction to Kant’s ethics. Sections devoted to each main formulation of the categorical imperative. Also includes discussions of Kant’s view of the nature of moral philosophy, the good will, virtue and vice, moral motivation, and autonomy. Bibliography, links to other Internet resources. Updated every few years.

    Find this resource:

  • Nargon, Steve. Kant in the Classroom.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Provides copious information about the lectures on moral philosophy, as well as the student notes on those lectures: the time period of the lectures from which the notes dates, which texts were used in those lectures, where the student notes are located now, whether they have been published and translated, and so on. Bibliography, glossary, and many useful links.

    Find this resource:

Anthologies

The anthology of broadest scope within Kant’s ethics is Hill 2009. It covers a wide range of topics. Although many of the essays are on challenging topics, they are, on the whole, fairly accessible. Somewhat narrower in scope, though still relatively broad, is Ameriks and Höffe 2009. Segments of this anthology focus on Kant’s influences, the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of Practical Reason, and Kant’s legal philosophy. What’s especially valuable about this collection is that all chapters are English translations of essays previously published only in German. Timmermann 2009, Reath and Timmermann 2010, and Denis 2010 are anthologies devoted to specific works by Kant; all are pitched to readers familiar with the text and secondary literature. Timmermann 2009 contains eleven essays on the Groundwork. Reath and Timmermann 2010 contain nine essays on the Critique of Practical Reason. Denis 2010 contains twelve essays on the Metaphysics of Morals. Although there are other commentaries and collections dedicated to these texts, these three reflect the most recent, expert-level work. They are suited to graduate students and above.

  • Ameriks, Karl, and Otfried Höffe, eds. Kant’s Moral and Legal Philosophy. Translated by Nicholas Walker. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511581618Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Fourteen essays in English by significant German Kant scholars, including Dieter Henrich, Wolfgang Kersting, Bernd Ludwig, and Annemarie Pieper. Topics cover the influence of Hutcheson, Wolf, and Baumgarten on Kant’s early moral thought, Kant’s conceptions of practical reason, maxims, and moral philosophy, and several topics specific to Kant’s political philosophy.

    Find this resource:

  • Denis, Lara, ed. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Diverse set of authors, topics, and approaches. Includes chapters on duties to oneself, duties to others, duties regarding animals, moral feelings, justice, virtue, reason, will, and desire. Contributors include Allen Wood, Paul Guyer, Stephen Engstrom, and Otfried Höffe.

    Find this resource:

  • Hill, Thomas E., Jr., ed. The Blackwell Guide to Kant’s Ethics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1002/9781444308488Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Topics range from such basic themes as the good will and formulations of the categorical imperative to aspects of Kant’s theories of justice and virtue. Essays accessible and interesting to a broad range of readers. Contributors include Arthur Ripstein, Stephen Darwall, Thomas Pogge, Marcia Baron, and Arnulf Zweig.

    Find this resource:

  • Reath, Andrews, and Jens Timmermann, eds. Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770869Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Essays tackle important, difficult questions raised by Kant’s second Critique. Topics include the fact of reason, incentives of pure practical reason, and the primacy of practical reason. Contributors include Heiner Klemme, Pauline Kleingeld, and Marcus Willaschek.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens, ed. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770760Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Chapters address questions raised by Kant’s most widely read ethical work. Topics include happiness, acting from duty, dignity and the formula of humanity, and freedom. Contributors include J. B. Schneewind, Paul Guyer, and Manfred Kuehn.

    Find this resource:

Bibliographies

Although many works on Kant’s ethics contain bibliographies helpful as a guide to further reading, the most comprehensive, regularly updated bibliography is Schroth 2012. This bibliography includes articles, books, and book chapters published on Kant’s moral philosophy. Most entries do not include annotations; there are more for recent entries than older ones. But the annotations which are provided, and which are often from the authors’ article abstracts or books’ tables of contents, are quite helpful. Most recent listings and annotations are in English; most older ones are in German.

Kant’s Ethical Works

As a wide ranging yet systematic philosopher, there are few works by Kant with no relevance to his ethics. The core works in moral philosophy, however, are Kant 1963a, Kant 1963b, and Kant 1969 (all cited under German). Also highly relevant are notes on Kant 1997 (cited under English Translations).

German

Kant’s foundational moral philosophy is found in Kant 1963a and Kant 1963b. Kant 1969 reflects Kant’s mature views about fundamental principles of ethics and politics for human beings. The student lecture notes capture a wide range of Kant’s thoughts on moral philosophy over three decades. The standard German edition of Kant’s complete works is Ausgabe der königlich preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, currently published by Walter de Gruyter. Kant 1986 (edited by Ludwig) offers a revised Rechtslehre that attempts to put sections in the order Kant intended and correct other errors in publication. Kant 1974–1975 contains student lecture notes on Kant’s lectures on moral philosophy—lectures he began giving long before he entered his “critical” period and that continued until soon before he wrote his Metaphysics of Morals. For those interested in the lectures on ethics, Kant 2004, edited by Stark, is a valuable supplement to those published in the Gesammelte Schriften.

  • Kant, Immanuel. “Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten.” In Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 4. Edited by Paul Menzer, 385–464. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1963a.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Originally published in 1785. This is a reprint of the 1903 edition. This is Kant’s foundational ethical work, and the one most studied by Anglo-American philosophers. This work sets out Kant’s conceptions of pure moral philosophy, moral motivation, the categorical imperative, and freedom.

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. “Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (1788).” In Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 5. Edited by Paul Natorp, 1–164. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1963b.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Originally published in 1788. This is a reprint of the 1908 edition. Kant’s critique of practical reason. It revises and further develops certain positions put forth in the Grundlegung—such as about freedom and moral motivation. Includes arguments concerning the practical postulates, the highest good, and the primacy of practical reason.

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. “Die Metaphysik der Sitten.” In Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 6. Edited by Paul Natorp, 203–494. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1969.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Originally published in 1797–1798. This is a reprint of the 1907 edition. This work presents Kant’s mature moral philosophy, as it applies to human beings. This work consists in two parts: the metaphysical first principles of right (Rechtslehre), and the metaphysical first principles of virtue (Tugendlehre).

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. “Vorlesungen über Moralphilosophie.” In Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 27. Edited by Gerhard Lehmann. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974–1975.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Kant’s lectures on moral philosophy span roughly thirty years, 1763/1764?–1793/1794, and thus are a valuable (if not completely reliable) resource for scholars of his moral philosophy and its development. Kant lectured from two text books by the Wolffian Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten: Initia Philosophiae Practicae and Ethica Philosophica. While most of these notes are published in Volume 27 of Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, an important set of notes on Kant’s lectures on ethics, the Mrongovius II notes from 1784–1785, are published in pages 597–642 of Volume 29 (1980).

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. Die Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre. Edited by Bernd Ludwig. Hamburg, West Germany: Meiner, 1986.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A revised edition of Kant’s Doctrine of Right. Ludwig argues that the text as originally published, contained numerous errors which distort Kant’s meaning and readers’ understanding. Ludwig explains the errors and their likely sources, as well as revising the text so that it reflects the organization he believes Kant intended.

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. Vorlesung zur Moralphilosophie. Edited by Werner Stark. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2004.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Contains Kaehler’s 1777 lecture notes along with substantial additional material, including an introduction by Manfred Kühn, an epilogue by Werner Stark, and appendices including, among other things, a chart showing which parts of the Kaehler notes correspond to which parts of Baumgarten’s textbooks.

    Find this resource:

English Translations

There are many English translations of Kant’s works on moral philosophy. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991–) is generally considered authoritative. Kant 1996 contains English translations of Kant’s Groundwork, second Critique, and Metaphysics of Morals. Kant 1997 contains translations of the lectures on ethics. These are entirely in English. The German text of the Groundwork is included side by side with the English translation in Kant 2011. The English translation here is a modification of that found in Kant 1996.

  • Kant, Immanuel. Practical Philosophy. Edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Includes the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Critique of Practical Reason, and The Metaphysics of Morals, and several relevant essays, such as “On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice.” Glossaries and brief introductions are included.

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. Lectures on Ethics. Edited by Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind. Translated by Peter Heath. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781107049512Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Selections from Herder lecture notes c. 1762–1764, Collins notes on moral philosophy lectures c. 1774–1777, selections from the Mrongovius II notes of 1784–1785, and the Vigilantius notes on Kant’s lectures on the metaphysics of morals of 1793–1794. An introduction by J. B. Schneewind, glossaries, and explanations of names are included.

    Find this resource:

  • Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A German-English Edition. Edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor and Jens Timmermann. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2011.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511973741Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Timmermann’s revision of the Gregor translation of the Groundwork with additional scholarly notes on the text and translation. Contains bilingual index.

    Find this resource:

Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Much scholarship on Kant’s ethics operates by attending closely to individual works—to considering the aims and structures of these works, and to analyzing the arguments and positions advanced therein. There are many commentaries on and guides to Kant’s major works in ethics. Guyer 2007 and Sedgwick 2008 should be helpful for undergraduates encountering the Groundwork (cited under English Translations) for the first time. Both are philosophically sophisticated, but aimed at students relatively new to philosophy in general and Kant in particular. Sedgwick 2008 is more of a passage-by-passage commentary than is Guyer 2007. Two important single-author commentaries aimed at scholars are Allison 2011 and Timmermann 2009. Each has much to say for it; each is distinctive. Allison reads a bit more like a normal book at times and critically discusses much contemporary secondary literature as well as being historically rich. The slimmer Timmermann 2007 is more of a passage-by-passage commentary. Timmermann 2007 is notable in part for its interpretation of the relation among the formula of universal law and the other formulations of the categorical imperative. Paton 2008 is not a commentary, strictly speaking. But much of this highly influential work focuses on central topics of the Groundwork, most notably the categorical imperative in its various formulations. Of the many collections concerning the Groundwork, two that are especially noteworthy are Höffe 1989 and Timmermann 2009. Höffe 1989 is more of a genuine cooperative commentary; it includes a mix of pieces in German, English, and French. Timmermann 2009 is a more topic-driven collection, with an international selection of contributors providing essays in English. Several pieces in the Höffe 1989 have been influential.

  • Allison, Henry E. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.

    DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199691531.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A philosophically rich commentary which pays significant consideration to Kant’s philosophical predecessors and contemporaries and draws on a wide range of Kant’s works, lectures, and handwritten notes. Places significant interpretive focus on the structure of the Groundwork and on Kant’s conception of the autonomy of the will.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. Kant’s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Reader’s Guide. London: Continuum, 2007.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Provides the reader with an introductory overview, then guides the reader through the preface and each of the Groundwork’s three sections. Some discussion of important secondary literature. Includes study questions. Suitable as a textbook.

    Find this resource:

  • Höffe, Otfried, ed. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten: Ein Koorpertiver Kommentar. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Essays by eighteen authors, including Rüdiger Bittner, Karl Ameriks, Thomas Pogge, Onora O’Neill, and Henry Allison. Essays in English, German, and French. Topics include the enterprise of the Groundwork, the good will, respect for the law, hypothetical and categorical imperatives, homo phenomenon and homo noumenon, and autonomy.

    Find this resource:

  • Paton, H. J. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2008.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Has done much to shape the Anglo-American understanding of Kant’s ethics in general and the Groundwork in particular. Although the categorical imperative is the focus, the book contains discussions of duty, the good will, reverence for the law, practical reason, the intelligible world, freedom, and more. First published in 1947.

    Find this resource:

  • Sedgwick, Sally. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: An Introduction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511809538Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A commentary designed with the undergraduate in mind. Leads the reader through the text nearly paragraph by paragraph. Extremely helpful explanations of Kant’s views about freedom and his responses to Hume, Leibniz, and others. Explicit argument reconstructions. Suitable as a textbook.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511487316Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    This is a detailed, close commentary. It includes six appendices on such important topics as Kant’s project of a metaphysics of morals and Schiller’s criticism of Kant on acting from duty. It also includes a glossary, with entries on such topics as autonomy, happiness, maxims, and reverence.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens, ed. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770760Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Less attention to the formula of universal law than one might expect. Much attention to the argument from freedom in the third section of the Groundwork. Other topics which receive attention include Kant’s conception of character, the role of examples in ethics, and Kant’s critique of “spurious principles of morality.”

    Find this resource:

Critique of Practical Reason

Beck 1960 is a classic, highly influential single-author commentary on the Critique of Practical Reason (Kant 1996, cited under English Translations) which provides a comprehensive treatment of the text. Höffe 2002 is a comprehensive, cooperative commentary. Chapters are keyed to various sections of the text, so that collectively they completely cover the text. Chapters do not always group sections of text chronologically; this occasional deviation allows for better coverage of particular topics, such as the fact of reason. Reath and Timmermann 2010 is more topic-driven than Beck 1960 and less exhaustive than Höffe 2002. It includes a diverse set of expert, international contributors; all contributions are in English.

  • Beck, Lewis White. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A classic commentary which continues to influence philosophical interpretation and debate of the second Critique, particularly within the English-speaking world.

    Find this resource:

  • Höffe, Otfried. Immanuel Kant: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2002.

    DOI: 10.1524/9783050050317Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A cooperative commentary in twelve chapters. German and English, with most chapters in German. Contributors include Karl Ameriks, Eckart Föster, Allen Wood, Reinhard Brandt, and G. Felicitas Munzel.

    Find this resource:

  • Reath, Andrews, and Jens Timmermann, eds. Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770869Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Nine essays by an international group of specialists, addressing such topics as the fact of reason, the incentives of pure practical reason, and the antinomy of practical reason. The anthology begins with a chapter on the origin and purpose of the second Critique.

    Find this resource:

Metaphysics of Morals

Although the two main parts of the Metaphysics of Morals (the Rechtslehre and Tugendlehre, cited under English Translations) are often studied separately, some commentaries cover the work as a whole. Gregor 1963 is the essential English-language commentary. Timmons 2002 and Denis 2010 are less exhaustive and more topic-driven than Gregor 1963. Each features the perspectives of a diverse set of specialists. Several pieces in Timmons have been influential already. Denis 2010 includes important recent work through which the reader can grasp the current state of relevant debates.

  • Denis, Lara, ed. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Topics include Kant’s theories of possession and punishment, his conception of the innate right of freedom, the primacy of perfect duties to oneself, moral feelings, and duties regarding animals. The collection begins with a chapter on the genesis of the Metaphysics of Morals and ends with a chapter on the Tugendlehre as normative ethics.

    Find this resource:

  • Gregor, Mary J. Laws of Freedom: A Study of Kant’s Method of Applying the Categorical Imperative in Kant’s Metaphysik der Sitten. Oxford: Blackwell, 1963.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    The classic English-language study. Includes discussion of Kant’s project of a metaphysics of morals and the divisions of moral philosophy, as well as detailed discussions of specific duties as articulated and argued for in the Metaphysics of Morals.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmons, Mark, ed. Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Several of these chapters have been influential: Stephen Engstrom’s chapter on virtue and Paul Guyer’s on Kant’s deduction of the principles of right. Several chapters consider the relation between Kant’s doctrines of right and virtue, which receive roughly equal attention within the collection.

    Find this resource:

Doctrine of Right

For those new to Kant’s philosophy of right, Flikschuh 2000 is a helpful introduction. For scholars, Byrd and Hruschka 2010 and Ludwig 1988 are recommended. For those primarily interested in Kant’s theory of right as a systematic political philosophy, Ripstein 2009 and Mulholland 1990 are recommended, as well as the more accessible Flikschuh 2000. Byrd and Hruschka 2010 is especially well suited for people with a strong interest in the history of legal and political philosophy. Ripstein 2009 is especially effective at making Kant’s political philosophy come to life. Ludwig 1988 is a valuable commentary philosophically, but is famous in part for its arguments concerning the proper ordering of sections in the Doctrine of Right.

  • Byrd, B. Sharon, and Joachim Hruschka. Kant’s Doctrine of Right: A Commentary. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511712050Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A detailed, scholarly, philosophical commentary. Informed by a wide range of Kant’s writings, notes, and lectures and illuminated by consideration of relevant literature available at the time of the writing of the Rechtslehre.

    Find this resource:

  • Flikschuh, Katrin. Kant and Modern Political Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511487187Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Situates Kant’s theory of right in relation to other important political philosophies, both modern and contemporary, showing what is distinctive and important about it. Distinguishes Kant’s own philosophy of right from contemporary (loosely) Kantian liberalism. Well suited to use as a textbook.

    Find this resource:

  • Ludwig, Bernd. Kant’s Rechtslehre. Hamburg, West Germany: Meiner, 1988.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    In German. Provides a detailed, scholarly analysis of Kant’s Rechslehre arguments. Early chapters explore problematic aspects of the Rechtslehre as originally published and reconstruct the organization of the text as Kant intended its sections to be arranged. Includes an outline of Ludwig’s reconstruction of the structure of the Rechtslehre.

    Find this resource:

  • Mulholland, Leslie Arthur. Kant’s System of Rights. New York: Columbia University Press, 1990.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Aims to provide a moral basis for Kant’s theory of right, grounding it in the categorical imperative. Although it covers main themes, topics, and arguments from the Doctrine of Right, it is not strictly speaking a commentary on it.

    Find this resource:

  • Ripstein, Arthur. Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    An interpretation and defense of Kant’s political philosophy based primarily on the Rechtslehre. The authors’ discussions of such issues as external freedom, consent, and equality reveal the vitality and significance of Kant’s philosophy of right. Treats Kant’s theory of right as independent of his theory of ethics.

    Find this resource:

Doctrine of Virtue

Although it is not precisely a commentary on the Doctrine of Virtue, Betzler 2008 is a collection focused on the part of Kant’s practical philosophy covered in the Doctrine of Virtue, including virtue, virtues, duties of duties to oneself, duties of respect, and duties of love. Trampota, et al. 2013 is a comprehensive, collective commentary on the Doctrine of Virtue by a diverse, international group of scholars.

  • Betzler, Monika, ed. Kant’s Ethics of Virtue. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2008.

    DOI: 10.1515/9783110209655Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A collection of eleven essays by a diverse range of contributors, including Marcia Baron, Stephen Darwall, Philip Stratton Lake, Robert Johnson, and Elizabeth Anderson. Although not strictly speaking a commentary on the Doctrine of Virtue, the essays in this collection draw heavily on this text and deeply explore issues and questions raised by it. Several essays explore the relation between Kantian ethics and virtue ethics. Although there is much here for scholars, there is much for ethicists as well.

    Find this resource:

  • Trampota, Andreas, Oliver Sensen, and Jens Timmerman, eds. Kant’s “Tugendlehre”: A Comprehensive Commentary. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2013.

    DOI: 10.1515/9783110229875Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Eighteen contributors, including established and emerging scholars from Germany, Italy, the United Kingdom, and the United States. This is a traditional commentary in that it attempts to be genuinely comprehensive in its coverage of the text. Essays focus on such topics as duties of respect, virtue and its ends, duties to oneself as an animal and moral being, and moral feelings.

    Find this resource:

Lectures on Ethics

Although it is not a philosophical commentary, an invaluable, comprehensive, and regularly updated resource for those interested in Kant’s lectures—on ethics or anything else—is Kant in the Classroom. It provides information on the notes, whether and where they are published and translated, current location, and provenance. Information, including table of contents, of the textbooks Kant used in his moral philosophy courses. Site tells how many times courses were taught, when, and how the courses were titled or announced. Schmucker 1961 provides background about Kant’s philosophical influences and development that is helpful for understanding the lectures. Kant in the Classroom is in English; Schmucker 1961 is in German. See Kant 1997, cited under English Translations.

  • Nargon, Steve. Kant in the Classroom.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    This site, which covers the full range of Kant’s classroom work, contains sections specific to Kant’s lectures on moral philosophy. Bibliography, glossary, and useful links.

    Find this resource:

  • Schmucker, Josef. Die Ursprünge der Ethik Kants in seinen vorkritischen Schriften und Reflektionen. Meisenheim, West Germany: Verlag Anton Hain KG, 1961.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Especially helpful for understanding Kant’s lectures on ethics is chapter 5 (pp. 278–394), which explores relations between Kant’s ethical thought and that of Alexander Baumgarten, whose textbooks Kant used as a basis for his lectures on ethics. In German.

    Find this resource:

Freedom

Freedom is fundamental to Kant’s practical philosophy. Transcendental freedom is a crucial presupposition of his ethics; autonomy the heart of it. Wood 1984 analyzes Kant’s attempt to reconcile noumenal freedom with phenomenal determinacy, and its implications for Kant’s ethics. Although not written as an introduction to the topic, it is an excellent starting point. Allison 1990 is essential reading: a rigorous examination of Kant’s theory of freedom, from spontaneity through autocracy; most subsequent work on the topic refers to it. McCarty 2009 covers much of the same ground (though in less textual depth) as Allison 1990 and engages critically with it while arguing for alternative positions. Most saliently, McCarty argues for metaphysical reading of the distinction Kant makes between appearances and things in themselves, whereas Allison conceives of Kant’s distinction as between two standpoints. Frierson 2003 grapples with a deep, pervasive problem about Kant’s theory of freedom with respect to human moral agents: a tension between Kant’s commitment in his theoretical philosophy and foundational moral theory to the position that we are transcendentally free and his commitment in his moral anthropology that we can influence one another empirically in morally significant ways. Korsgaard 1996 reconstructs Kant’s argument that the moral law is the law of a free will, and that we must regard ourselves as free and thus bound by the moral law; she uses a distinction between theoretical and practical standpoints in order to defend Kant from charges of ontological dualism and incoherence regarding moral imputability. Guyer 2000 argues that freedom, as an end, plays a more fundamental role in Kant’s moral theory than has traditionally been acknowledged—a role at odds with common understandings of Kant as a deontologist. Schneewind 1998 traces the development of the concept of autonomy that reaches realization in Kant’s moral theory. O’Neill 2003 draws sharp contrasts between Kant’s conception of autonomy and those prevalent in much contemporary moral and political philosophy (e.g., on bioethics, consent, paternalism). It is essential reading for anyone who wishes to understand Kant’s distinctive conception of autonomy.

  • Allison, Henry. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139172295Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Highly influential treatment of Kant’s moral theory. Important discussion of the Third Antinomy, transcendental and practical freedom, the empirical and the intelligible character, practical and transcendental freedom, the “reciprocity thesis,” the Wille-Willkür distinction, the fact of reason, respect, radical evil, the “incorporation thesis,” and virtue and holiness.

    Find this resource:

  • Frierson, Patrick R. Freedom and Anthropology in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511498121Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Frierson attempts to reconcile Kant’s claims about our transcendental freedom, a fundamental presupposition of Kant’s moral philosophy, with his claims about empirical influences on human moral development and agency, a presupposition of Kant’s view that anthropology is morally relevant.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. “Kant’s Morality of Law and Morality of Freedom.” In Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. By Paul Guyer, 129–171. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173339.006Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that Kant regards freedom as a fundamental, necessary end, recognition of which is an essential starting point for moral reasoning (rather than a consequence of it). Originally published in Kant and Critique: New Essays in Honor of W. H. Werkmeister, edited by R. M. Dancy (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic, 1993), pp. 43–89.

    Find this resource:

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. “Morality as Freedom.” In Creating the Kingdom of Ends. By Christine M. Korsgaard, 159–187. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139174503.007Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that the key to defending Kant against some important and intuitively compelling objections to his account of freedom is distinguishing properly between practical and theoretical reason and their respective deliberative and explanatory standpoints. Originally published in Kant’s Practical Philosophy Reconsidered, edited by Yirmiyahu Yovel (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic, 1989), pp. 23–48.

    Find this resource:

  • McCarty, Richard. Kant’s Theory of Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199567720.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents Kant’s theory of action as combining metaphysical freedom and psychological determinism. Original and illuminating discussion of Kant on maxims, radical evil, virtue, and more at the intersection of Kant’s theories of freedom, action, and ethics. Much critical attention to competing views.

    Find this resource:

  • O’Neill, Onora. “Autonomy: The Emperor’s New Clothes.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77 (Suppl.) (2003): 1–21.

    DOI: 10.1111/1467-8349.00100Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Provides an account of Kant’s notion of autonomy as concerns principles of action (as opposed to agents or ways of choosing), showing how it is important and distinctive. Illuminates relations among Kantian autonomy, rationality, and morality. Distinguishes Kant’s notion of autonomy and from those of J. S. Mill and Gerald Dworkin.

    Find this resource:

  • Schneewind, Jerome B. The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Focused on the 17th and 18th centuries, this book traces the development of the idea of autonomy from the roots of the natural law tradition through Kant’s moral philosophy. Schneewind allows his readers to appreciate the significance of Kant’s contribution to moral philosophy and its debts to its predecessors.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. “Kant’s Compatibilism.” In Self and Nature in Kant’s Philosophy. By Allen W. Wood, 73–101. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1984.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Situates Kant’s view of freedom of the will in relation to compatibilism and incompatibilism by articulating Kant’s unique “incompatibilist compatibilism.” Discussion of transcendental and practical freedom (negative and positive), autonomy and heteronomy, intelligible and empirical causality, weakness of will and radical evil.

    Find this resource:

Practical Reason

Ethics is the domain of practical reason; much of Kant’s foundational work in ethics concerns Kant’s own theory of practical reason. Hill 1992 is an accessible introduction to Kant’s conception of practical reason, and Kant’s grounding of morality in pure practical reason. It is well suited to undergraduates both because of its style and because of its focus on the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, with which students are likely to be most familiar. Reath 2006 also provides a concise, relatively accessible Groundwork-based treatment of Kant’s grounding of morality—especially the formula of universal law—in pure practical reason. The most accessible of the pieces focused on the second Critique is Gardner 2006. Gardner 2006 elucidates much that is distinctive and important about Kant’s theory. This piece delves into aspects of Kant’s theory as he presents it in the Critique of Practical Reason. This piece discusses Kant’s thesis regarding the primacy of practical reason and the theological postulates. Other aspects of Kant’s theory of practical reason, as articulated in the second Critique, are explored closely in Pieper 2009; the focus here is the concept of the object of pure practical reason, the categories, and the relations among the moral law, practical judgment, and action. Beck 1960 provides a comprehensive analysis of Kant’s theory of practical reason through a commentary on the second Critique. Its influence in the field makes it essential reading. By far the most original and challenging work on Kant’s theory of practical reason is Engstrom 2009. Like Hill 1992 and Reath 2006, Engstrom 2009 explores Kant’s grounding of the categorical imperative in pure practical reason. Key to Engstrom 2009, however, is his interpretation of Kant’s conception of practical reason as a capacity for knowledge of the good. Engstrom 2009 ranges widely over Kant’s texts; it draws heavily on the Groundwork and second Critique, but also on the introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of Judgment, and much else.

  • Beck, Lewis White. A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    This influential commentary on the second Critique is essential reading for those who wish to understand Kant’s theory of practical reason. Includes discussions of Kant’s conception of practical reason; reason, will, wish, and choice; practical concepts and judgment.

    Find this resource:

  • Engstrom, Stephen. The Form of Practical Knowledge: A Study of the Categorical Imperative. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Cognitivist conceptions of practical reason have a long history, reaching back to Plato. Engstrom develops Kant’s version of this approach in relation to Kant’s conceptions of will, choice, and wish; thought, judgment, and validity; morality and the categorical imperative.

    Find this resource:

  • Gardner, Sebastian. “The Primacy of Practical Reason.” In A Companion to Kant. Edited by Graham Bird, 259–273. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1111/b.9781405111973.2006.00022.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Distinguishes between two ways to construe the primacy of practical reason. Explores the primacy of practical reason both (narrowly) as a principle set forth in the Dialectic of the Critique of Practical Reason and (broadly) as a distinctive feature of Kant’s critical philosophy.

    Find this resource:

  • Hill, Thomas E., Jr. “Kant’s Theory of Practical Reason.” In Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory. By Thomas E. Hill Jr., 123–146. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents main features of Kant’s theory of practical reason, drawing primarily on the Groundwork. Discusses hypothetical imperatives, negative freedom, autonomy, and moral principles. Reprint of the original version published in The Monist 72 (1989): 363–383.

    Find this resource:

  • Pieper, Annemarie. “‘On the Concept of an Object of Pure Practical Reason’: Chapter 2 of the Analytic of Practical Reason.” In Kant’s Moral and Legal Philosophy. Edited by Karl Ameriks and Otfried Höffe, and translated by Nicholas Walker, 179–197. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511581618Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Analyzes fourteen pages in which Kant defines the object of pure practical reason, explicates the categories through which pure practical reason determines its object. Originally published as “Zweites Hauptstück (57–71).” In Immanuel Kant: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, edited by Otfried Höffe (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2002), pp. 115–133.

    Find this resource:

  • Reath, Andrews. “The Categorical Imperative and Kant’s Conception of Practical Rationality.” In Agency and Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Theory. By Andrews Reath, 67–91. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1093/0199288836.003.0004Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Reath provides an account of Kant’s conception of practical reason and of the categorical imperative as the principle that most fully expresses its requirements. He is ultimately concerned to show how Kant derives morality from reason. Reprint of the original version published in The Monist 72.3 (1989): 384–410.

    Find this resource:

The Categorical Imperative

Commentators have been interested in many aspects of the categorical imperative. Among them, Kant’s identification of the rationally self-legislated categorical imperative as the supreme moral principle, how he argues for it, how we are bound by it, how the various formulations of it relate to one another, and how it grounds duties. Wood 2006 provides an accessible article-length account of Kant’s conception of the categorical imperative and relations among its formulations. An illuminating feature of this account is its discussion of Kant’s argument that only the categorical imperative, not the principles of his predecessors, can be the supreme moral principle. A more challenging article-length piece is Guyer 2000, which considers the relations among the formulae of the categorical imperative with special attention to what they contribute to Kant’s account of the real possibility of the categorical imperative. O’Neill 1989 principally concerns the question of what equivalence between the formulas of universal law and the formula of humanity might amount to. Kerstein 2002 provides a book-long examination of Kant’s criteria of a supreme moral principle and whether the formula of universal law or other candidates meet them. Timmermann 2007, which is a sophisticated, passage-by-passage commentary on the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, offers much careful, textually grounded argument regarding Kant’s conception of the categorical imperative, its justification, and the relations among the formulae. Paton 2008 is essential reading: it provides a systematic, highly influential explication of the various formulae and relations among them, situating the interpretation of the categorical imperative within a comprehensive account of Kant’s foundational moral theory. Engstrom 2009 presents a “practical-cognitivist” account of the categorical imperative within an account of practical reason as a capacity of knowledge of the good; while the book culminates in two chapters dedicated to interpretation and application of the categorical imperative, previous chapters provide accounts of practical reason, judgment, and the idea of a categorical imperative.

  • Engstrom, Stephen. The Form of Practical Knowledge: A Study of the Categorical Imperative. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents Kant as conceiving of practical reason as a capacity for knowledge of the good, and morality as consisting in knowledge of intrinsic goodness. Engstrom presents categorical imperative as a principle of “self-agreement.” His focus is the formula of universal law and the law of nature variant.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. “The Possibility of the Categorical Imperative.” In Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. By Paul Guyer, 172–206. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173339.007Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Explores the progression and relations among the formulations of the categorical imperative, with attention to what each formulation contributes to Kant’s account of how a categorical imperative is possible. Reprint of the original version published in Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 353–385.

    Find this resource:

  • Kerstein, Samuel. Kant’s Search for the Supreme Principle of Morality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511498206Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that Kant has eight criteria for the supreme principle of morality. Shows that these criteria are not met by several candidates for the supreme moral principles. Explores whether the categorical imperative—particularly the formula of universal law—meets these criteria.

    Find this resource:

  • O’Neill, Onora. “Universal Laws and Ends-in-Themselves.” In Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. By Onora O’Neill, 126–144. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Considers how we might best understand Kant’s claims that formulas of universal law and humanity are equivalent, and what each formulation contributes. Reprint of the original version published in The Monist 72.3 (1989): 341–361.

    Find this resource:

  • Paton, H. J. The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2008.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A seminal treatment of Kant’s conception of the categorical imperative, its formulations, its justification. Paton’s analyses of each formulation, their applications and implications, and the relations among the formulations continue to be influential. First published in 1946.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens. Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511487316Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents the formula of universal law as the “general form” of the categorical imperative and other formulas as variants of it which containing analogies drawing on earlier philosophical ideals (such as the Stoics’ notion of living in accordance with nature). Variants bring the categorical imperative “closer to feeling.”

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. “The Supreme Principle of Morality.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Edited by Paul Guyer, 342–380. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1017/CCOL052182303XSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents Kant’s view of what the supreme principle of morality is supposed to do and be like and why the categorical imperative is it. Explains the relations among the formulations of the categorical imperative and the specific contributions of each. Discusses Kant’s critiques of previous moral systems.

    Find this resource:

Formula of Universal Law

The formula of universal law is widely regarded to be the basic form of the categorical imperative. Since Kant’s own day, commentators have tried to understand whether and how the first formulation of the categorical imperative, with its contradiction in conception and contradiction in will tests, is supposed to work. A classic work on Kant’s ethics that devotes substantial space to maxim formulation and testing by the categorical imperative is Nell 1975. It is detailed, systematic, and acute. The discussion of the categorical imperative is situated in a broader treatment of Kant’s moral theory. The other three are stand-alone articles. Korsgaard 1996 is doubtless among the most influential pieces on this or any version of the categorical imperative. While arguing for her own preferred interpretation of the contradiction in conception test, Korsgaard 1996 offers a systematic examination of three main interpretations of the contradiction in conception test in relation to Kant’s examples, Hegelian objections, and the contradiction in the will test. So much that has been written about the formula of universal law subsequently refers to it that it is essential reading on the topic. Herman 1993b and Herman 1993a each seek a better understanding of the categorical imperative by bringing the formula of universal law contradiction tests to bear on maxims of violence (in Herman 1993a) and beneficence (in Herman 1993b). These are especially rich pieces philosophically and ethically.

  • Herman, Barbara. “Murder and Mayhem: Violence and Kantian Casuistry.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 113–131. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993a.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Herman articulates and uses the formula of universal law-based “CI procedure” she takes to be suggested by the Groundwork. Develops notions of “generic maxims” to be tested and “deliberative presumptions” that result. Reprint of the original version published in The Monist 72 (1989): 411–431.

    Find this resource:

  • Herman, Barbara. “Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 45–72. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993b.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Analyzes Kant’s Groundwork argument for beneficence via the contradiction in will test; explain how “true needs” operate within that test. Develops a notion of a “community of mutual aid.” Reprint of the original version published in Ethics 94 (1984): 577–602.

    Find this resource:

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. “Kant’s Formula of Universal Law.” In Creating the Kingdom of Ends. By Christine M. Korsgaard, 77–105. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139174503.004Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Delineates and critically compares three interpretations of the formula of universal law contradiction in conception test: logical, teleological, and practical. Argues for the superiority of the practical interpretation. Reprint of the original version published in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1985): 24–47.

    Find this resource:

  • Nell, Onora. Acting on Principle: An Essay in Kantian Ethics. New York: Columbia University Press, 1975.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Highly influential classic work on Kant’s ethical theory, which allots great time and care to the formula of universal law, its contradiction tests, and related issues such as maxims formulation and the problem of relevant descriptions.

    Find this resource:

Formula of Humanity

Many find Kant’s second main formulation of the categorical imperative more intuitive than the first, and more relevant to Kant’s system of ethical duties. The influential, much-cited, must-read work here is Korsgaard 1996. She provides accounts of humanity, Kant’s argument for the formula of humanity, what it means to treat humanity as an end itself, and fundamental aspects of Kant’s theory of value. Timmermann 2006 offers sharp and interesting criticisms of Korsgaard 1996 as well as putting forth his own alternative interpretations. Dean 2006 and Sensen 2011 are far broader in scope than the formula of humanity itself. Both delve into Kant’s theory of value and make distinctive claims about the humanity and its value. As books, both also afford their authors opportunity to engage critically and at length with other commentators. The focus of Dean 2006 is his identity of humanity with a good will, which he takes to be something that some human agents may lack but others have. Thus, a distinct and provocative aspect of Dean’s interpretation is that it does not suppose that every human agent has humanity in her person. Much of his book argues for this position and defends the interpretation against anticipated objections regarding its practical implications. Sensen 2011 focuses on how we should construe the dignity of humanity in light of Kant’s theory of value and the relevant texts. Central to the book’s argument is that Kant does not regard dignity as an absolute, independent value, but rather as relational status of elevation designating something as above something else. Sensen 2011 is distinguished by its close readings, its exhaustive examination of passages in which Kant talks of dignity, and its persuasive use of earlier examples of the “traditional” paradigm of dignity.

  • Dean, Richard. The Value of Humanity in Kant’s Moral Theory. Oxford: Clarendon, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1093/0199285721.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues for the interpretation of humanity as a good will, and defends it from objections. There are chapters on the formula of humanity and how duties follow from it, as well as chapters on nonhuman animals and the way bioethicists talk about “respect for autonomy.”

    Find this resource:

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. “Kant’s Formula of Humanity.” In Creating the Kingdom of Ends. By Christine M. Korsgaard, 106–132. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139174503.005Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Understands humanity as the capacity to set ends (and thus as broader than personality), but which is fully realized only when the choice of ends is fully rational; reconstructs Kant’s Groundwork argument for the formula of humanity as a regress upon conditions of value; presents humanity as having “value-conferring status.” Reprint of the original version published in Kant-Studien 77 (1986): 183–202.

    Find this resource:

  • Sensen, Oliver. Kant on Human Dignity. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2011.

    DOI: 10.1515/9783110267167Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Rejects a common conception of Kant’s notion of dignity of humanity as an absolute inner value on the basis of which we should respect human beings, in favor of an interpretation which equates dignity with sublimity and (relational) elevation of free beings.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens. “Value without Regress: Kant’s ‘Formula of Humanity’ Revisited.” European Journal of Philosophy 14.1 (2006): 69–93.

    DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2006.00244.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Offers a critical assessment of Korsgaard and original, alternative interpretations of Kant’s argument for the formula of humanity, what Kant means by “humanity” in the context of the requirement that we treat it as an end in itself, and how reason “determines” value within Kant’s system.

    Find this resource:

Formula of the Kingdom of Ends

Questions here concern how this formulation relates to other others, as well as whether to understand the kingdom of ends as a political ideal or some sort, or a purely ethical, religious, or metaphysical ideal. Hill 1992 analyzes Kant’s conception of a kingdom of ends, suggests what it adds to the previous formulations of the categorical imperative, and explains its operation as a moral standard. Hill argues that the formula of the kingdom of ends is superior to the formula of universal law in several respects. It’s a very short, rather accessible piece. Less accessible but more scholarly is Flikschuh 2009. In presenting an account of the kingdom of ends as an ethical ideal that each rational will generates through moral self-legislation, Flikschuh 2009 aims to displace Rawlsian readings of the kingdom of ends, according to which it is a quasi-political ideal of co-legislation. Flikschuh 2009 draws on the text of the second section of the Groundwork, as well as on broader considerations of the differences between Kant’s conceptions of ethical and political commonwealths. It also offers an account of the relation between the kingdom of ends formulation and the other formulae.

  • Flikschuh, Katrin. “Kant’s Kingdom of Ends: Metaphysical, Not Political.” In Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Edited by Jens Timmermann, 119–138. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770760.008Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Interprets Kant’s conception of a kingdom of ends as a metaphysical ideal, one of an ethical union under God. Argues against Rawlsian interpretations of the kingdom of ends as a quasi-political commonwealth.

    Find this resource:

  • Hill, Thomas E., Jr. “The Kingdom of Ends.” In Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant’s Moral Theory. By Thomas E. Hill Jr., 58–66. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Interprets this formula as contributing something new and important, by asking us to think in terms not of isolated maxims, but rather in terms of a system of moral principles. Originally published in Proceedings of the Third International Kant Congress, edited by Lewis White Beck (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel, 1972).

    Find this resource:

Moral Motivation

Kant’s claim that action from duty alone has moral worth has been a lightning rod for critical attention. Herman 1993 is an influential attempt to defend Kant’s claims about the special moral worth of acting from duty by providing an account according to which the motive of duty can operate in the background as well as in the foreground. This approach has been influential. Baron 1995 takes up and modifies this approach, bring her version of it to bear in explicit defense against criticisms of Kant’s ethics as alienating because of its account of action from duty. The most scholarly pieces on moral motivation are Timmermann 2009, Engstrom 2010, and Guyer 2010. Timmermann 2009 focuses on the Groundwork treatment of the distinction between acting from duty and acting from inclination; his is one of these three that bears most directly on Kant’s claims about the special moral worth of action from duty. Engstrom 2010 provides an in-depth analysis of the Critique of Practical Reason and discussion of the incentives of pure practical reason, and the contrast there between respect for the law and incentives of self-love and self-conceit. Engstrom explains that the moral law’s positive effect on feeling is indirect: the elevating feelings of respect for the law and esteem for ourselves as its legislators are preceded by the humiliating feeling of the moral law’s striking down of our self-conceit. Guyer 2010 addresses Kant’s moral psychology more comprehensively than the others: first, it discusses respect for the law in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the second Critique, and the Doctrine of Virtue; second, it discusses also moral feeling, conscience, and self-esteem, and their relation to respect for the law and various pathological feelings. All three of these approaches are interpretively, philosophically, and ethically interesting.

  • Baron, Marcia. “Is Acting from Duty Morally Repugnant?” In Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology. By Marcia Baron, 117–145. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1995.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Interprets the motive of neither as merely a back-up motive nor as operative only episodically, but rather as a pervasive motive that regulates how one lives. Revised and reprinted from the original version published as “The Alleged Moral Repugnance of Acting from Duty,” Journal of Philosophy 81.4 (1984): 197–200.

    Find this resource:

  • Engstrom, Stephen. “The Triebfeder of Pure Practical Reason.” In Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide. Edited by Andrews Reath and Jens Timmermann, 90–118. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770869Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Incisive examination of Kant’s second Critique account of how the moral law moves us to action in the absence of any antecedent feelings attuned to the moral law.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. “Moral Feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Edited by Lara Denis, 130–151. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Traces the development of Kant’s account of moral feelings and motivation through the Groundwork, second Critique, and the Doctrine of Virtue, with emphasis on the last. Develops a multistage model of the phenomenal etiology of morally worthy action, in which a variety of feelings, as well as conscience, are implicated.

    Find this resource:

  • Herman, Barbara. “On the Value of Acting from the Motive of Duty.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 1–22. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that the motive of duty can function not only as an agent’s immediate or primary motive for action, but also as a limiting condition, which determines if and when she acts on other motives. Reprint of the original version published in Philosophical Review 90 (1981): 359–382.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens. “Acting from Duty: Inclination, Reason, and Moral Worth.” In Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Edited by Jens Timmermann, 45–62. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511770760.004Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Clarifies and defends Kant’s position that only action from duty is morally worthy. Argues actions from duty can satisfy inclinations (which are only indirectly with volition and action), whereas only action from duty can satisfy reason (which is directly concerned with volitions and their grounds).

    Find this resource:

Virtue

Baxley 2010 is book-length treatment of Kant’s theory of virtue. It is attentive to a broad range of Kant’s text and to some historical and developmental considerations, while being systematic in its overall approach. Baxley’s development of Kant’s conception of autocracy in relation to his conception of autonomy is a contribution in its own right. Denis 2006 provides a brief, accessible introduction to Kant’s conception of virtue, virtues, and vices. Guyer 2000 provides a textually rich account of virtue and duties of virtue, in part by situating Kant’s conception of virtue in relation to his conceptions of a good will, moral worth, moral perfection, and merit. Engstrom 2002 analyzes Kant’s conception of virtue through Kant’s characterization of virtue as inner freedom. This piece has had a significant influence on subsequent work on Kant’s conception of virtue; it is important for scholars. Grenberg 2005 is focused on a single virtue (or virtuous meta-attitude), humility. But the book has much of interest to say about virtue and the human struggle for it. Even more than Grenberg 2005, Louden 2000 develops Kant’s theory of virtue by situating it within his theory of human nature. The perspective of Louden 2000 is valuable in part for the range of Kant’s writings and lectures on which it draws.

  • Baxley, Anne Margaret. Kant’s Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511779466Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    An account of Kant’s theory of virtue which takes the autocracy of pure practical reason as central. Explores the relation between virtue and the good will, the moral psychology of virtue, and Kant’s conflict with Schiller regarding the nature of virtue.

    Find this resource:

  • Denis, Lara. “Kant’s Conception of Virtue.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Edited by Paul Guyer, 505–537. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1017/CCOL052182303XSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Briefly traces the history of virtue theory prior to Kant. Focuses on explicating Kant’s theory of virtue and his account of particular virtues and vices. Considers Kant’s criticisms of his predecessors and responses to Kant’s theory of virtue.

    Find this resource:

  • Engstrom, Stephen. “The Inner Freedom of Virtue.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays. Edited by Mark Timmons, 289–315. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Influential account of virtue as a strong expression of inner freedom, the capacity for moral self-constraint essential to human morality.

    Find this resource:

  • Grenberg, Jeanine. Kant and the Ethics of Humility: A Story of Dependence, Corruption, and Virtue. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511627859Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    An account of Kantian virtue which treats humility as central. Discusses relations between humility and self-respect, and between moral and epistemic humility. Distinguishes Kantian moral humility with other conceptions of humility, and contrasts it with arrogance.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. “Moral Worth, Virtue, and Merit.” In Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. By Paul Guyer, 289–329. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173339Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Delineates different ways Kant uses the word “Tugend” or phrases including it and argues for a specific relation among them—for example, that virtue as a strong, persistent endeavor to comply with duty is a product of virtue as pure moral motivation.

    Find this resource:

  • Louden, Robert B. Kant’s Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Draws on Kant’s theories of education, religion, art, anthropology, and history in order to present a rich, empirically informed account of Kantian ethics in general and his theory of virtue in particular.

    Find this resource:

The Highest Good

Either Wood 2009 or Beiser 2006 would make a good starting point for exploring the topic. Wood 2009 is essential reading on the topic of the highest good, both because of its tremendous influence on subsequent scholarly discussion of the topic, and because it situates the topic within a broader treatment of Kant’s views about God, religion, and morality. Beiser 2006 situates Kant’s views about the highest good in relation to relevant views of Kant’s predecessors and contemporaries, as well as in the context of related positions of Kant (e.g., about belief in God). Reath 1988 distinguishes between two conceptions of the highest good and argues one should be preferred to the other; he favors the highest good as a “secular” ideal as opposed to a “theological” one. Engstrom 1992 provides a careful, compelling account of the highest good as the complete object of pure practical reason. Engstrom 1992 focuses more narrowly on the highest good itself than do Wood 2009 and Beiser 2006, and more on the argument of the second Critique than do Guyer 2000 and Reath 1988. Guyer 2000 considers and resolves problems within Kant’s ethics concerning a realization of the highest good within the natural world. Problematic claims include those suggesting that nature somehow intends our freedom, virtue, and happiness; that our moral end must include not only virtue but also happiness; and that the highest good may be realized not by each individual being maximally virtuous and therefore maximally happy, but rather by later generations benefiting from the moral efforts of their forbearers. Beiser 2006 argues against reading Kant’s conception of the highest good as a secular ideal, and suggests that it is due to misunderstandings of Kant’s conception of the highest highest good that some commentators have seen as two distinct conceptions of it, one according to which it is realized in this world and one in the next.

  • Beiser, Frederick C. “Moral Faith and the Highest Good.” In The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy. Edited by Paul Guyer, 588–629. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006.

    DOI: 10.1017/CCOL052182303XSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Presents Kant’s conception of the highest good in relation to the postulates of God and immortality, moral faith, and the primacy of practical reason. Argues that Kant’s conception of the highest good cannot, without distortion, be regarded as a secular ideal.

    Find this resource:

  • Engstrom, Stephen. “The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51.4 (1992): 747–780.

    DOI: 10.2307/2107910Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Shows how the highest good follows from the moral law as the complete object of pure practical reason. Explains why virtue is both necessary and sufficient for the goodness of happiness. Considers whether we should understand our duty to be to promote or to achieve the highest good.

    Find this resource:

  • Guyer, Paul. “Nature, Freedom, and Happiness: The Third Proposition of Kant’s Idea for a Universal History.” In Kant on Law, Freedom, and Happiness. By Paul Guyer, 372–407. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2000.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173339.013Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Attempts to resolve apparent inconsistencies in foundational tenets of Kant’s moral philosophy and propositions in Idea concerning the realization of the highest good in nature over the course of human history.

    Find this resource:

  • Reath, Andrews. “Two Conceptions of the Highest Good in Kant.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1988): 593–619.

    DOI: 10.1353/hph.1988.0098Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Distinguishes between “theological” and “secular” accounts of the highest good in Kant’s philosophy. Disputes proportionality between virtue and happiness as essential to Kant’s conception of the highest good. Argues in favor of the secular account and considers the role of institutions in its realization.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. Kant’s Moral Religion. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2009.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    This seminal work in Kant’s philosophy of religion is dedicated in part to reconstructing sympathetically Kant’s account of the highest good as the complete object of pure practical reason. Defends the consistency of Kant’s moral theory inclusion of such an object with its insistence on the autonomy of the will. Originally published in 1970.

    Find this resource:

Radical Evil

Allison 1990 is a particularly influential account of radical evil, and thus is important background. It is also helpful because the discussion of radical evil takes place within a book-long, systematic treatment of Kant’s moral theory. Allison 1990 provides illuminating and influential discussions of the conception of radical evil, its levels, and its relations to the moral disposition and will. Similar things can be said about Wood 1999. The interpretations of radical evil—its content and Kant’s argument for it—that Allison 1990 and Wood 1999 offer contrast, with Wood 1999 being more anthropological and Allison 1990 more a priori. (The whole approach of Wood 1999 is more anthropological than that of Allison 1990; this difference is not limited to their analyses of radical evil.) Wood is interested in the social (as well as the individual) aspects of how human beings can and should seek to overcome their propensity to evil. Frierson 2003 treats radical evil within his book-length exploration of tensions between a few of Kant’s key positions at the intersection of ethics and anthropology. It is a less comprehensive treatment of Kant’s ethics than Wood 1999, concerned with resolving a narrowly defined problem. Sussman 2005 is an original and interesting article-length treatment of radical evil. In addition to offering its own compelling interpretation, the piece includes ample attention to the text of Religion, with discussion of the three predispositions, the three degrees of evil, and other essential aspects of the doctrine.

  • Allison, Henry. Kant’s Theory of Freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139172295Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Radical evil is the subject of chapter 8 (pp. 146–161). Argues that while Kant’s claim about the radical evil in human nature may appear to be merely an empirical generalization, the claim must be read as a synthetic a priori one, and thus as requiring a deduction. Allison attempts to provide one.

    Find this resource:

  • Frierson, Patrick R. Freedom and Anthropology in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511498121Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    The book concerns a tension among Kant’s views about freedom and empirical influences on human beings. Chapter 5 (pp. 95–135) reconstructs Kant’s proof of radical evil in human nature, arguing that it involves a priori and empirical arguments. Treats radical evil as crucial to understanding a human being’s good will.

    Find this resource:

  • Sussman, David. “Perversity of the Heart.” Philosophical Review 114.2 (2005): 153–177.

    DOI: 10.1215/00318108-114-2-153Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Sussman argues that radical evil—and the active antagonism toward morality it involves—is necessary for the progression of (finite, temporal, natural) human beings toward the realization of our practical reason. Philosophically and interpretively rich; engaging for the ethicist as well as the Kant scholar.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139173254Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Chapter 9 (pp. 283–320) argues that only empirical arguments can establish whether human beings have a propensity to evil. Wood gives an “anthropological reading” of the content of radical evil; he associates radical evil with our social nature, identifying ambition, a social passion, as “the root of all evil.”

    Find this resource:

Historical Perspectives

Schneewind 1998 traces the development of the idea of autonomy which culminates in Kant’s moral philosophy. The book has great scope, but the focus on autonomy provides a through line. Kant himself is discussed only quite late in the book; but the earlier chapters provide valuable background for appreciating Kant’s contribution to moral philosophy. Irwin 2009 is the third and final volume in a major work by Irwin on the history of moral philosophy. This last volume contains reconstructions and analyses of a variety of important arguments within Kant’s ethics, relating them to arguments and problems in earlier and later moral philosophers. Kuehn 2001 is a biography that reveals a great deal about Kant’s intellectual influences and development. Among the topics covered are many that shed light on Kant’s ethical thought and its development. That is the sole topic of Ward 1972. Ward 1972 provides a supplement—or perhaps corrective—to overviews of Kant’s ethics that focus on his mature views and his most explicitly ethical works, ignoring the lectures and precritical writings. This is an accessible, brief volume that keeps its focus on Kant’s developing thought, and covers the duration of his thinking life. Schmucker 1961 and Schwaiger 2009 specifically concern Kant’s early moral thought and crucial influences upon it. Schmucker 1961 (in German) is more comprehensive than Schwaiger 2009, which focuses on the topic of obligation, and goes far more in depth. Beck 1969 and Beiser 1987 are not focused exclusively on Kant’s ethics, but set Kant in the context of German intellectual and cultural history. Beiser 1987 more than Beck 1969 gives a sense of the intellectual climate in which Kant was working, and his own influence on the debates in which he participated.

  • Beck, Lewis White. Early German Philosophy: Kant and His Predecessors. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Situates Kant’s philosophy, and the philosophy of earlier philosophers such as Albertus Magnus, Meister Eckhart, Leibniz, Wolff, Mendelssohn, and Herder within the context of German intellectual and cultural history. Considers the ways Kant’s and earlier German philosophy was shaped by dominant political, educational, and religious beliefs, practices, and institutions.

    Find this resource:

  • Beiser, Frederic C. The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Plunges the reader into Kant’s intellectual context, life, and development, providing a sense of the philosophical debates that shaped Kant’s thought and to which he contributed. Explores relation of Kant to Spinoza, Wolff, Hamann, Jacobi, Mendelssohn, Herder, Garve, Reinhold, Fichte, Maimon, and others.

    Find this resource:

  • Irwin, Terence. The Development of Ethics: A Historical and Critical Study. Vol. 3, From Kant to Rawls. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Seven chapters of rigorous analysis of Kant on reason, inclination, and desire; happiness and self-interest; the categorical imperative; autonomy; the good will; respect; duty and virtue; God and the highest good. Irwin also considers Kant’s criticisms of eudaimonism and Kant’s metaethics. Subsequent chapters consider Kant through lenses of his critics.

    Find this resource:

  • Kuehn, Manfred. Kant: A Biography. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A philosophically and historically rich biography. Over four hundred pages of text, preceded by a chronology of Kant’s life and work and proceeded by over one hundred pages of notes and bibliography. Provides an illuminating account of Kant’s intellectual influences and the social and intellectual context in which he worked.

    Find this resource:

  • Schmucker, Josef. Die Ursprünge der Ethik Kants in seinen vorkritischen Schriften und Reflektionen. Meisenheim, West Germany: Verlag Anton Hain KG, 1961.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Exploration of Kant’s early writings in moral philosophy and the philosophical influences on the development of Kant’s ethical thought, such as Hutcheson, Crusius, Wolff, and Baumgarten, and what Kant adopted, rejected, or modified from them. No index, but a detailed, informative analytic table of contents is extremely helpful. In German.

    Find this resource:

  • Schneewind, Jerome B. The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Focused on the 17th and 18th centuries, traces ideas about morality and self-governance so as to show the roots of Kant’s conception of autonomy, as well as the significance and distinctiveness of his contribution to the history of moral philosophy.

    Find this resource:

  • Schwaiger, Clemens. “The Theory of Obligation in Wollf, Baumgarten, and the Early Kant.” In Kant’s Moral and Legal Philosophy. Edited by Karl Ameriks and Otfried Höffe, and translated by Nicholas Walker, 58–73. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511581618Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Shows where Baumgarten’s conception of obligation departs from Wolff and which aspects most influenced Kant. Originally published as “Zur Theorie der Verbindlichkeit bei Wolff, Baumgarten und dem frühen Kant,” in La filosofia practica tra metafisica e antropologia nell’età di Wolff e Vico, edited by G. Cacciatore, et al. (Naples, Italy: Guida, 1999), pp. 323–340.

    Find this resource:

  • Ward, Keith. The Development of Kant’s View of Ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Ward illuminates the teleological aspects of Kant’s ethics, as well as the significance of his philosophy of religion to his moral philosophy. The antinomies, practical postulates, and categorical imperative are discussed at length.

    Find this resource:

Constructivism

There is a strand of Kant interpretation, beginning with John Rawls, according to which Kantian morality is constructed through the operation of reason. Rawls 1999a is a classic, well-developed constructivist interpretation of Kant’s ethics. According to Rawls 1999a, the CI-procedure itself is not constructed, but merely makes explicit requirements implicit in everyday operations of practical reason; that the CI-procedure is based in a conception of persons as free and equal, reasonable, and rational; and that the content of morality is constructed. Rawls 1999b is presentation of Rawls’s own theory of justice as Kantian, where constructivism is taken to be central to Kant’s approach to moral philosophy. These pieces are worth reading in part because Rawls’s constructivist interpretation of Kant has been so influential, shaping the thought of many luminaries in Kantian moral and political philosophy, such as Korsgaard, O’Neill, Hill, Herman, and Reath. O’Neill 1989 analyzes Rawls’s Kantian constructivism, particularly as developed in A Theory of Justice, and considers arguments from critics alleging it does not represent a genuine alternative to realism and relativism. She does much to clarify Rawls’s approach as well as those of his critics before offering a variant of his approach. Korsgaard 1996 is a hugely influential work which presents Kantian constructivism as uniquely able to address fundamental problems of obligation, motivation, and normative authority that have plagued moral philosophy since antiquity. Many Kantians are not constructivists, and do not think Kant is best interpreted along constructivist lines. Kain 2004 argues against constructivist interpretations of Kant specifically by arguing that a proper understanding of Kant’s conception of self-legislation is antagonistic to constructivist interpretations of it. Kain develops an account of Kant’s view of self-legislation as (in part) an alternative to theological voluntarism. Many are confused about what exactly Kantian constructivism amounts to. Krasnoff 2007 attempts to clarify what constructivism is, and whether it makes sense to attach that label to Kant.

  • Kain, Patrick. “Self-Legislation in Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” Archiv für Geschicthte der Philosophie 86 (2004): 257–306.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Kain argues that Kant’s conception of self-legislation is different from and incompatible with contemporary constructivist interpretations. A careful, scholarly argument which is illuminating with respect to the development of Kant’s own views, and as well as of interest with respect to the merits and pedigree of “Kantian” constructivism.

    Find this resource:

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora O’Neill. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511554476Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Four chapters trace attempts to answer “the normative question” from Socrates to the present. Chapters 3 (pp. 90–130) and 4 (pp. 131–166) develop a Kantian constructivism, according to which there are (as realists claim) objective criteria for moral judgment, but (in opposition to the realist) these criteria emerge from practical reasoning itself.

    Find this resource:

  • Krasnoff, Larry. “How Kantian Is Constructivism?” In German Idealism. Edited by Klaus Brinkmann, 257–283. London: Routledge, 2007.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    The answer: “not very.” Krasnoff untangles the various notions identified with “constructivism.” He then considers on which if any of those construals of constructivism Kant’s practical philosophy is appropriately described as “constructivist.” Reprint of the original version published in Kant-Studien 90 (1999): 385–409.

    Find this resource:

  • O’Neill, Onora. “Constructivism in Ethics.” In Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. By Onora O’Neill, 206–218. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Considers Rawls’s constructivism and objections to it. Advocates an alternative form of constructivism that relies on abstraction, not on idealization. Reprint of the original version published in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1988–1989): 1–17.

    Find this resource:

  • Rawls, John. “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory.” In John Rawls: Collected Papers. Edited by Samuel Freeman, 303–358. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999a.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Elucidates the Kantian roots of “justice as fairness.” Fundamental principles of justice emerge from reasonable agreement among free and equal persons in an idealized choice situation. Revised and reprinted from the original version published in Journal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515–572.

    Find this resource:

  • Rawls, John. “Themes in Kant’s Moral Philosophy.” In John Rawls: Collected Papers. Edited by Samuel Freeman, 497–528. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999b.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Rawls articulates what he takes to be the distinctively constructivist aspects of Kant’s moral thought. Originally published in Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The “Three Critiques” and the “Opus Postumum,” edited by Eckart Förster (Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989), pp. 81–113.

    Find this resource:

Applications

Kant’s ethics is not only of scholarly interest, but of practical interest as well. This can be seen in a vast array of works that discuss Kant’s own views about concrete moral matters, or that draw out practical implications of his views. The best of these works illuminate foundational aspects of Kant’s moral theory while at the same time showing what the theory amounts to in practice. Altman 2011 is the most extensive single-author application of Kant’s moral philosophy, addressing a wide range of topics. It is accessible enough for undergraduates. Wood 2008 covers fewer topics, but the book as a whole provides a fuller and deeper treatment of Kant’s ethical theory. Early chapters discuss foundational issues in Kant’s moral theory. Kain 2009 provides a scholarly exploration of a crucial issue for many questions of application: the scope and basis of the moral status of a person. Implications of Kant’s theory for abortion, euthanasia, and many other bioethical issues hinge on this. Herman 1993a and Herman 1993b make vivid and vital Herman’s influential interpretation of Kant’s moral thought (and the CI-procedure) through application to particular moral issues concerning violence in one case and beneficence in another.

  • Altman, Matthew C. Kant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011.

    DOI: 10.1002/9781118114162Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Considers what Kant’s moral philosophy implies about a number of controversial contemporary issues, including ethical treatment of animals, the environment, universal healthcare, patient autonomy, the death penalty, same sex marriage, “mail-order” marriages, and broader issues of social justice.

    Find this resource:

  • Herman, Barbara. “Murder and Mayhem: Violence and Kantian Casuistry.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 113–131. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993a.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues for a “deliberative presumptions” against generic maxims of killing persons for convenience. Illuminating discussion of violence and coercion against persons. Reprint of the original version published in The Monist 72 (1989): 411–431.

    Find this resource:

  • Herman, Barbara. “Mutual Aid and Respect for Persons.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 45–72. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993b.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Develops a notion of “a community of mutual aid” and explores issues about the scope and stringency of the duty of aid members of that community. Reprint of the original version published in Ethics 94 (1984): 577–602.

    Find this resource:

  • Kain, Patrick. “Kant’s Defense of Human Moral Status.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 47.1 (2009): 59–102.

    DOI: 10.1353/hph.0.0083Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Does Kant regard all members of our biological species as persons, and if so, does he have any principled basis for this view? Kain provides a scholarly argument for the affirmative answer to both questions, along with critical treatment of Kantian alternatives to Kant’s own view on human moral status.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. Kantian Ethics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Four late chapters (11–14) focus on social justice (pp. 193–205), punishment (pp. 206–223), sex (pp. 224–239), and lies (pp. 240–258). The discussion of humanity in chapter 5 (pp. 85–105), for example, discusses the moral status of the human fetus and of nonhuman animals.

    Find this resource:

Animals and Environment

Kant’s view that all duties to animals and nature are indirectly duties to oneself with regard to animals and nature have inspired resourcefulness among philosophers aiming to defend or modify Kant’s position. Hill 1991 (originally published in 1983) is most broadly an environmental focus but farthest from Kant’s texts. Hill 1991 suggests that there are noncontroversial ideals of character and particular attitudes and traits—e.g. humility, gratitude, and self-acceptance—to which one can appeal in order to explain what’s wrong with someone willing to destroy the natural environment. The remaining pieces are principally concerned with nonhuman animals. Denis 2000 and Kain 2010 attempt to stay closest to Kant in their approach. Kain 2010 has more to say about competing views and moral status than Denis and draws on a wider range of texts than does Denis 2000; Denis 2000 considers practical implications more than Kain 2010. Timmermann 2005 stays quite close to Kant as well, though modifies Kant’s position somewhat by rejecting Kant’s designation of duties regarding animals as “indirect” duties to oneself. Wood 1998 and Korsgaard 2005 make innovative Kantian arguments—which illuminate Kant’s ethical theory in various ways—in order to improve upon Kant’s own stated position on duties regarding animals. Wood 1998, for example, affirms Kant’s “logocentism,” according to which all duties are grounded n the value of rational nature, but rejects the “personification principle,” according to which only persons are objects of respect.

  • Denis, Lara. “Kant’s Conception of Duties Regarding Animals: Reconstruction and Reconsideration.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 17.4 (2000): 405–423.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Reconstructs Kant’s argument for duties with regard to (in Ansehung) nonhuman animals. Argues that such duties are well grounded within Kant’s system and in light of his understanding of human nature and psychology. Argues also that these duties are more robust, with more significant moral implications, than critics have typically acknowledged.

    Find this resource:

  • Hill, Thomas E., Jr. “Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving the Natural Environment.” In Autonomy and Self-Respect. By Thomas E. Hill Jr., 104–117. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511609237.009Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Explores the resources of Kantian ethics for explaining what’s wrong with destroying aspects of the natural environment. Reprint of the original version published in Environmental Ethics 5 (1983): 211–224.

    Find this resource:

  • Kain, Patrick. “Duties Regarding Animals.” In Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide. Edited by Lara Denis, 210–233. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Articulates Kant’s views of moral status and the nature of animals. Critiques interpretations of our obligations regarding animals offered by Korsgaard, Wood, and Timmermann. Draws on Kant’s lectures on physical geography, which have not been translated into English, and which provide rich insight into Kant’s understanding of animals’ nature.

    Find this resource:

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. “Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals.” In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Vol. 25. Edited by G. B. Peterson, 77–110. Salt Lake City: Utah University Press, 2005.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Uses a Kantian constructivist approach to argue animals and their interests make direct normative claims on moral agents; we are committed to regarding our animal nature, not just our rational nature, as an end in itself.

    Find this resource:

  • Timmermann, Jens. “When the Tail Wags the Dog: Animal Welfare and Indirect Duty in Kantian Ethics.” Kantian-Review 10.1 (2005): 128–149.

    DOI: 10.1017/S1369415400002168Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Offers an interpretation of “indirect duty”; he argues such duties cannot capture the ways in which animals are proper objects of moral concern. Rejects Korsgaard’s and Wood’s Kantian alternatives. Revises Kant’s account so that duties regarding animals are “direct” duties to oneself and still not duties to animals.

    Find this resource:

  • Wood, Allen W. “Kant on Duties Regarding Non-Rational Nature I.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 72 (Suppl.) (1998): 189–210.

    DOI: 10.1111/1467-8349.00042Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Takes the formula of humanity to enjoin respect for rational nature in rudimentary or partial forms, allowing it give a better account of our moral relations to other animals and to the natural world.

    Find this resource:

Sex

Herman 1993 is the essential reading on this topic, in part because its publication broke ground by making a serious attempt to understand and find something of value in Kant’s accounts of sex and marriage. It has been highly influential and continues to be cited frequently. A driving question in Herman 1993, which accounts for some of the piece’s importance, is that of whether and how entering a juridical relation of marriage can solve the pervasive, apparently intractable, and intensely intimate ethical problems Kant associates with sexual desire and its expression. O’Neill 1989 illuminates the formula of humanity through application to intimate relationships. This piece is least useful for one interested in a scholarly examination of Kant’s published writings on sex. Denis 1999 considers Kant’s condemnation of “unnatural” sex as a violation of a duty to oneself. This is the only piece among the three to focus on unnatural sex in particular; it is also centrally concerned with understanding how considerations of natural teleology may play a role in determining our duties to ourselves as animal and moral beings. The interpretation that emerges is sympathetic to Kant’s approach in broad outline, but critical with respect to certain of Kant’s specific arguments and conclusions, for example, regarding the wrongness of homosexual sex as such.

  • Denis, Lara. “Kant on the Wrongness of ‘Unnatural’ Sex.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 16.2 (1999): 225–248.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Uses the formula of humanity to examine Kant’s prohibition of unnatural sex as a violation of a duty to oneself as an animal and moral being. Considers Kant’s teleological conception of our animal nature and its organs and drives.

    Find this resource:

  • Herman, Barbara. “Could It Be Worth Thinking about Kant on Sex and Marriage?” In A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity. Edited by Louise Antony and Charlotte Witt, 49–67. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1993.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that Kant’s views of sexuality align with a dominant strand of contemporary feminist thought, and explores the resources of Kant’s approach—and especially its reliance on legal marriage of a certain well-defined sort—to solve the fundamental moral problems posed by sexual desires and sexual relations.

    Find this resource:

  • O’Neill, Onora. “Between Consenting Adults.” In Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. By Onora O’Neill, 105–125. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Uses the contexts of work and intimate sexual relationships to explore what it means to treat others merely as a means as opposed to as an end in itself. Reprint of the original version published in Philosophy and Public Affairs 14.3 (1985): 252–277.

    Find this resource:

Suicide and Euthanasia

Kant makes some claims that suggest that suicide is always a violation of a duty to oneself; and others that suggest that killing oneself only on certain maxims constitutes the vice of suicide. Cholbi 2000 and Hill 1991 provide reasons to believe that Kant’s ethics is less condemnatory of suicide that it often appears to be; Cholbi 2000 stays closer to Kant’s textual discussions of suicide than does Hill 1991. Unna 2003 offers a scholarly refutation of approaches such as those of Hill 1991 and Cholbi 2000, arguing that Kant is deeply committed to and uncompromising in his condemnation of suicide. Velleman 1999 argues for a similar position to Unna 2003, but on grounds more systematic than scholarly.

  • Cholbi, Michael J. “Kant on the Irrationality of Suicide.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 17.2 (2000): 159–176.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Cholbi delineates three arguments Kant gives against suicide. He argues for one of them; and argues that if Kant’s position of suicide is grounded in this argument, it is less absolutist and more attractive than commonly thought.

    Find this resource:

  • Hill, Thomas E., Jr. “Self-Regarding Suicide: A Modified Kantian View.” In Autonomy and Self-Respect. By Thomas E. Hill Jr., 85–103. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511609237.008Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Reconstructs Kant’s position on suicide, and argues for modifications to it based largely on Kant’s own foundational principles and what they imply about proper attitudes and ideals regarding the value of human life. Originally published in Suicide and Life-Threatening Behavior 13.4 (1983).

    Find this resource:

  • Unna, Yvonne. “Kant’s Answers to the Casuistical Questions Concerning Self-Disembodiment.” Kant-Studien 94 (2003): 454–473.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Draws on the Vigilantius notes on Kant’s lectures on the metaphysics of morals—as well as other lecture notes, published works, and handwritten notes—to argue that Kant is unwavering in his prohibitions on suicide and self-mutilation. Highly scholarly; historically sensitive and informative.

    Find this resource:

  • Velleman, J. David. “A Right to Self-Termination?” Ethics 109.3 (1999): 606–628.

    DOI: 10.1086/233924Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues that we do not have a right to end our lives simply because they no longer seem worth living to us. We degrade humanity in our person, violating its dignity, if we are willing to end our lives in order to satisfy ends of relative value.

    Find this resource:

Lying

Kant’s apparently absolutist position on lying—prohibiting it even to save an innocent person from her would-be murderer—has prompted much scholarly attention. Korsgaard 1996 is interested both in what various formulations of the categorical imperative imply about lying, and using this exploration of the categorical imperative to make a distinction Kant did not make between ideal and nonideal theory. She argues that while the formula of universal law does not support Kant’s view that lying is always wrong, the formulas of humanity and the kingdom of ends do. This is because they invoke an ideal of human relationships which is fundamental to Kant’s moral system, which can be seen as an “ideal theory.” This essay’s Kantian treatment of the issue reflects interestingly on the categorical imperative and moral theory, but is less scholarly than Mahon 2003. By attending carefully to Kant’s Doctrine of Virtue and lectures on ethics, Mahon 2003 provides a nuanced account of Kant’s conception of lying in so far as it is ethically prohibited; this allows him to show that Kant’s ethical prohibition on lying forbids a narrower set of things than one might think. Sedgwick 1991 and Weinrib 2008 focus specifically on Kant’s juridical (as opposed to ethical) prohibition on lying, as well as on Kant’s controversial essay “On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy.” Though these two essays cover some common ground between them, each is illuminating in distinctive ways.

  • Korsgaard, Christine M. “The Right to Lie: Kant on Dealing with Evil.” In Creating the Kingdom of Ends. By Christine M. Korsgaard, 133–158. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

    DOI: 10.1017/CBO9781139174503.006Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Argues in part that cases in which Kant’s position on lying rings false are those in which we are dealing with evil; to address cases like this, we need principles of “non-ideal theory.” Reprint of the original version published in Philosophy and Public Affairs 15.4 (1986): 325–349.

    Find this resource:

  • Mahon, James. “Kant on Lies, Candour and Reticence.” Kantian Review 7 (2003): 102–133.

    DOI: 10.1017/S1369415400001758Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    A nuanced explication of Kant’s prohibition on lying, which focuses on delineating the scope of the prohibition. Argues that once we appreciate the precise nature and scope of the prohibition on lying, Kant’s view is more plausible and attractive than it has often been taken to be.

    Find this resource:

  • Sedgwick, Sally. “On Lying and the Role of Content in Kant’s Ethics.” Kant-Studien 82.1 (1991): 42–62.

    Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Analyzes Kant’s controversial essay “On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy.” Emphasizes that Kant is considering lying from the perspective of right rather than ethics, and not doing applied law (let alone applied ethics) in the essay; his interests there are more formal or foundational.

    Find this resource:

  • Weinrib, Jacob. “The Juridical Significance of Kant’s ‘Supposed Right to Lie.’” Kantian Review 13.1 (2008): 141–170.

    DOI: 10.1017/S1369415400001126Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »

    Situates Kant’s position in “On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy” within his juridical account of lying in the Doctrine of Right. Explicates Kant’s view of lying as contrary to a rightful condition among human beings, and thus as a juridical wrong even when no particular person is wronged.

    Find this resource:

back to top

Article

Up

Down