Practical Moral Skepticism
- LAST REVIEWED: 15 December 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 27 April 2017
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0343
- LAST REVIEWED: 15 December 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 27 April 2017
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0343
Introduction
The issue of why be moral is one of the most intractable in moral philosophy. Plato is the first Western philosopher to address it extensively in The Republic. In the dialogue, Thrasymachus asserts that justice is the interest of the stronger, which he illustrates with the story of the ring of Gyges. The ring, when turned a certain way, makes its bearer invisible and thus able to escape detection when acting immorally. Glaucon challenges Socrates to demonstrate that the just life is more advantageous than the unjust life, or, that rationality requires being a moral person. In the 1600s, Thomas Hobbes addresses the skeptic who wants to be shown that every morally required action is rationally required and who understands rational action to be identified with self-interested action, or, action that best satisfies one’s desires or preferences. Hobbes develops his contractarian moral theory in the context of his attempt to defeat a self-interest based skeptic about moral action. Henry Sidgwick, in the late 1800s, argues that there are two equally compelling sets of reasons—moral and prudential—and that there is no way to adjudicate between them such that one always overrides the other. Immanuel Kant argues that reason requires that one follow duty rather than inclination even when following morality thwarts all one’s inclinations, self-interested or otherwise. David Hume believes that most of us have reasons to be moral grounded in the universal sentiment of sympathy or benevolence, but for others, such as the sensible knave, who lacks such feelings, Hume offers self-interested reasons having to do with peace of mind, reputation, and the like, and, if these be rejected, there is nothing more to say. Aristotle’s approach was similar on this last point, as he addresses his discussion of this issue to those who are already at least somewhat disposed to morality or at least not pigheaded about the arguments for following it. Since the time when these historical figures tackled the issue of why be moral, it has been largely ignored. We might extract from error theory, the view that all moral talk is false because there are no moral facts, that the practical skeptic’s challenge is moot. Recently, however, the topic of practical skepticism has garnered significant attention since 1986 when David Gauthier, in the spirit of Hobbes, proposed a self-interest based contractarian theory with an eye to defeating the skeptic who wants it to be shown that every morally required action is rationally required. This theory of rational action and choice, known as the expected utility theory, is appealed to heavily by economists and social scientists and is taken by Gauthier to be the parameter within which skepticism needs to be defeated for the reason that self-interested action is seen as action that is most in opposition to moral action. Hence, if the skeptic is successfully defeated, the moral philosopher will have defeated the worst-case scenario against morality. Some philosophers after Gauthier adhere to the Hobbesian strategy and propose different answers to the skeptic, while others propose different moral theories and in their context address skepticism, and still others challenge the way the skeptic’s position is traditionally defined. Other challenges are more indirect, aiming at the expected utility theory, the notion of self-interest as desire satisfaction, and the legitimacy of the desires that rationality dictates the agent to satisfy. An issue related to skepticism is that of the possibility of rational amoralism. The amoralist recognizes that there is a reason to act morally but denies the force of moral reasons, believing that they do not necessarily motivate. Internalists about reasons and motives, who endorse a position known as motivational internalism, deny that amoralism is a tenable position, while externalists, who deny the necessary connection between reasons and motives, insist that it is. The vast amount of literature on this debate takes the issue of skepticism to a deeper level than merely demonstrating the overridingness of moral reasons. A similar point can be made about the issue of the authority of moral reasons, or whether moral reasons necessarily bind a rational person. Demonstrating that acting in morally required ways is rationally required addresses the theoretical skeptical challenge, while demonstrating that moral reasons necessarily take on, or grip, rational agents addresses the practical skeptical challenge.
Responses to Skepticism
Self-Interest Based
Some responses to skepticism are grounded in self-interest because they take self-interest to be the action most in opposition to moral action and to be grounded in a theory of rational choice and action. Gauthier 1967 and Gauthier’s work (1982) lay the groundwork for his development of a self-interest based contractarian moral theory and a response to skepticism from its framework in the 1986 book. Gauthier 1986 revived the issue of practical skepticism and generated a huge body of literature on skepticism and contractarianism. MacIntosh 1995 attempts to develop it further in terms of self-interest. Brink 1990 defends an egoistic justification that is grounded in psychological continuity of the self. DeBruin 1995 expresses doubts that this kind of defeat of skepticism can ever be successful. Hampton 2002 modifies self-interest based contractarianism with the Kantian assumption that all persons have intrinsic value, stressing the importance of self-interest but tempering it so that a moral theory does not endorse exploitation. Bloomfield 2008 argues that in light of many problems with grounding a defeat of skepticism in terms the skeptic would accept, we should turn around the skeptical question into showing that it is in one’s self-interest not to be self-respecting. Sterba 2012 believes that arguing in terms of either reasons of self-interest or moral reasons will beg the question either in favor of skepticism or in favor of morality and offers an attempt to reconstrue the why be moral question in a way that both sides would find acceptable. Tiberius 2013 examines several well-being theories that ground a defeat of skepticism in prudential reasons and offers promising empirical evidence that morality can be grounded in prudential reasons.
Bloomfield, Paul. “Why It’s Bad to Be Bad.” In Morality and Self-Interest. Edited by Paul Bloomfield, 251–271. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Notable for flipping the “why be moral?” question to “How does it harm one to be immoral?” Argues that the “pleonectic,” who acts immorally and always gets away with it, is arrogant because he believes he is superior to others and deserves more than they do because of his cleverness and who he is. Shifts the burden to the immoralist to show that it’s in one’s self-interest not to be self-respecting.
Find this resource:
Brink, David O. “Rational Egoism, Self, and Others.” In Identity, Character, and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology. Edited by Owen Flanagan and Amelie Oksenberg Rorty, 339–378. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 1990.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Significant for defending a new, neo-Aristotelian, egoistic justification for acting morally that is grounded in psychological continuity of the self and extending it to others, even to a wider, public community in which persons are unknown to each other.
Find this resource:
DeBruin, Debra A. “Can One Justify Morality to Fooles?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (1995): 1–31.
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1995.10717402Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Comprehensive account of various forms of rationalist accounts offered to defeat the skeptic who demands that we demonstrate the obligatory force of morality. Argues that rationalism need not convince amoralists to be moral. Neither instrumentalist nor noninstrumentalist forms of rationalism can meet the demands of an internalist reason which has motivational force. Nor can rationalism meet the demands of an externalist reason taken in an instrumentalist or noninstrumentalist form.
Find this resource:
Gauthier, David. “Morality and Advantage.” Philosophical Review 76 (1967): 460–475.
DOI: 10.2307/2183283Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Pioneering paper putting forth the idea that a Hobbesian attempt to defeat skepticism by demonstrating that every morally required action is rationally required because it is in one’s self-interest is unsuccessful. Argues that, to defeat skepticism, we need to demonstrate the rationality of being a truly moral person who is disposed to morality and acts on this disposition even if the system of morality collapses. Useful for explaining Hobbes in terms of the Prisoner’s Dilemma.
Find this resource:
Gauthier, David. Morals by Agreement. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Landmark book reviving the Hobbesian self-interest based contractarian moral theory. Attempts to ground a defeat of skepticism in self-interest. Renowned for developing the idea that adopting a moral disposition of constrained maximization is rationally required because it is in one’s self-interest. It attempts to explain how the rationality of this disposition carries over to the acts expressing it, though not in a self-interested way.
Find this resource:
Gauthier, David. “Three against Justice: The Foole, the Sensible Knave, and the Lydian Shepard.” In Moral Dealing: Contract, Ethics, and Reason. Edited by David Gauthier, 129–149. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1990.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed examination of the relation between justice and self-interest through three skeptical characters. Hobbes’s Foole grounds the reason for making and following a moral contract in self-interest and thus can accept only a political solution to injustice. Hume’s Sensible Knave sees that following a general policy about virtue is wise but does not address exceptions. The Lydian shepherd challenges the rationality of the agreement of morality, demanding that we give justice intrinsic value. Reprinted from Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7, ed. P. A. French, T. E. Uehling Jr., and H. N. Wettstein, 11–29 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982).
Find this resource:
Hampton, Jean. “Feminist Contractarianism.” In A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity. 2d ed. Edited by Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt, 337–368. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues for modifying Hobbesian contractarianism to include the interests of all, particularly disenfranchised, groups, with the assumption that all persons have intrinsic value. Important because this modification extends the application of contractarianism to private relationships, with the aim of ending women’s oppression by disallowing exploitation of women.
Find this resource:
MacIntosh, Duncan. “Categorically Rational Preferences and the Structure of Morality.” In Proceedings of the Conference, “Modeling Rational and Moral Agents.” Edited by Peter Danielson, 282–301. Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science 7. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Defends the reduction of morality to rationality but argues that it is rationally obligatory to revise one’s preferences. Argues that it is irrational to have malevolent values, including slavish, bullying, and stingy ones, on the grounds that it is only rationally permissible to will to have values that one could will everyone to have in the same circumstances. Original way to defeat skepticism by showing that cooperation is rational with others who have rationally appropriate preferences.
Find this resource:
Sterba, James P. Morality: The Why and the What of It. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Novel attempt to defeat the skeptic by reconstruing the skeptic’s position to invoke non-question-begging reasons. Defends “morality as compromise,” according to which moral reasons are seen as a compromise between egoistic or self-interested reasons, and altruistic reasons, according to which each person ought to do what best serves the overall interest of others. Moral reasons override self-interested reasons, and the egoist and skeptic are defeated.
Find this resource:
Tiberius, Valerie. “Why Be Moral? Can the Psychological Literature on Well-Being Shed Any Light?” Res Philosophica 90.3 (July 2013): 347–364.
DOI: 10.11612/resphil.2013.90.3.3Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Examines three well-being theories’ answers to Glaucon’s challenge: mental state, desire or value, and eudaemonist. For each, the reason to be moral is at least partly empirical. Important for showing that psychological research shows that we have some reasons to do some moral things, though it does not show that moral reasons are overriding in every case.
Find this resource:
Dispositions and Actions
To defeat the skeptic fully, the traditional view is that we need to demonstrate that every morally required action is rationally required. Self-interest based contractarians aim to show that every morally required action is rationally required because it is in the agent’s self-interest. Gauthier 1984 examines whether this is the best way to defeat the skeptic and puts forward the idea that self-interestbased contractarianism shows that being morally disposed is rationally required because it is in the agent’s self-interest. Gauthier 1986 (cited under Self-Interest Based) develops this idea much further by arguing that the rationality of actions comes from the rationality of the disposition they express. Kavka 1978 and Parfit 1984 deny this connection between dispositions and actions in favor of the rationality of acts being independent of the rationality of dispositions, while Lewis 1984 also denies it in favor of a more complex view. Darwall 1986 discusses both sides and compares this debate about rationality to a similar one about morality. Superson 2009, in light of problems with both views, defends another thesis, according to which the rationality of dispositions and of acts should be judged interdependently.
Darwall, Stephen L. “Rational Agent, Rational Act.” Philosophical Topics XIV (1986): 33–57.
DOI: 10.5840/philtopics19861422Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Discusses the debate between Gauthier 1986 and Parfit 1984 about the connection between the rationality of dispositions and of acts in terms of the problem that some theories are indirectly individually self-defeating. Compares theories of rationality and theories of morality and argues that Gauthier’s approach to rationality seems analogous to character-based theories of morality but turns out to be end-based.
Find this resource:
Gauthier, David. “Deterrence, Maximization, and Rationality.” Ethics 94 (1984): 474–495.
DOI: 10.1086/292561Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Early work of this author that lays the groundwork for the Dependency Thesis in Gauthier 1986 (cited under Self-Interest Based) that if a disposition is rational to adopt, the acts it expresses are also rational. Argues in the context of nuclear deterrence.
Find this resource:
Gauthier, David. “Rethinking the Toxin Puzzle.” In Rational Commitment and Social Justice: Essays for Gregory Kavka. Edited by Jules L. Coleman and Christopher W. Morris, 47–58. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511527364.005Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Responds to critics about the Dependency Thesis who endorse the toxin puzzle case. Modifies earlier view to the view that rational deliberation concerning future-directed intentions must consider both the formation and the execution of the intention. Rationality is decided by what is the best course of action in terms of realizing one’s objectives that one can adopt as a whole.
Find this resource:
Kavka, Gregory. “The Toxin Puzzle.” Analysis 197 (1978): 33–36.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Offers an oft-cited counterexample to the thesis that a rational intention always issues in rational actions.
Find this resource:
Lewis, David. “Devil’s Bargains and the Real World.” In The Security Gamble: Deterrence Dilemmas in the Nuclear Age. Edited by Douglas MacLean, 141–154. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues against David Gauthier’s 1984 argument that if adopting a disposition is rational, rejecting the actions it requires is inconsistent. Defends the view that a person is a mixture of rationality and irrationality about dispositions and actions.
Find this resource:
Parfit, Derek. Reasons and Persons. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Landmark book that challenges many basic beliefs about morality and rationality, and offers the case of Kate, who is rational to work hard but whose working to exhaustion is irrational, as a challenge to the Gauthier 1986 (cited under Self-Interest Based) Dependency Thesis. Defends the Independency Thesis, according to which the rationality of dispositions and of acts is determined independent of each other.
Find this resource:
Superson, Anita M. The Moral Skeptic. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195376623.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed argument against Gauthier’s Dependency Thesis and in favor of the Interdependency Thesis, according to which the rationality of dispositions and of acts expressing them is determined interdependently. Important for defeating the action skeptic who wants it to be shown that every morally required act is rationally required since it promises to defeat the action skeptic and the disposition skeptic at once.
Find this resource:
Non-Self-Interest Based
Most moral philosophers who attempt to defeat practical skepticism do so in terms of a particular moral theory. Since Gauthier 1986 (cited under Self-Interest Based), several moral theories have been defended that have offered responses to the skeptic. Copp 1995 defends a society-centered moral theory that addresses the skeptic in terms of self-grounded rational choice, which is choice based on needs and values rather than self-interest. Darwall 2006 defends a Kantian second-person standpoint from which we understand the notions of claims and demands, second-personal reasons, responsibility, accountability, and the like, and only if one is in the circle where these terms are understood in light of each other can we have moral reasons.
Copp, David. Morality, Normativity, & Society. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed defense of a novel needs- and values-based society-centered moral theory, according to which a moral code is justified, relative to a society, if and only if the society would be rational to select it to serve as its social moral code. Rejects expected utility theory in favor of “self-grounded” rational choice, according to which having a basic need for something or a value yields a reason to secure, keep, or pursue it.
Find this resource:
Darwall, Stephen. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed defense of a Kantian second-person standpoint, according to which we have reasons grounded in reactive attitudes and the dignity of persons. The notions of second-personal authority to make reasons, valid claims or demands, second-personal reasons, responsibility, and accountability comprise an interdefinable circle, where each concept implies the others. Does not directly address skepticism but implies that the skeptic accepts only first-personal reasons and never breaks into the circle where moral reasons are possible.
Find this resource:
The Skeptic’s Challenge
The difficulty in defeating the practical skeptic has left some moral philosophers questioning whether the traditional view of the skeptic steeped in self-interest and preference satisfaction is plausible. Copp 1991 argues that self-interest based contractarianism defended by Hobbes and later by Gauthier 1986 can never succeed in defeating skepticism due to its constraints and grounding in expected utility theory. Copp 1997 goes further than Copp 1991 in arguing that there is no standpoint of reason simpliciter that would always dictate either self-interested or moral action. Finlay 2008 agrees and argues that we choose between self-interest and morality on the basis of our own preferences. Sterba 2012 finds that the traditional challenge is question-begging because the skeptic accepts only reasons of self-interest and the moralist accepts only moral reasons, and the author argues for a way to accommodate both reasons. Kavka 1984 weakens the skeptic’s demand so we can answer it; Superson 2009 strengthens it by expanding it to cover more cases of immoral action than self-interested action. Superson 2012 goes beyond Superson 2009 in proposing a more robust model of ideal rational agency than the preference-satisfaction model of the traditional skeptic that accords the privileged and the nonprivileged an equal perspective from which to ask what kind of action is rationally required. Copp 2007 examines what the skeptic’s question is really asking. Garner 2007 argues in favor of error theory, claiming that morality is fictional, as is practical skepticism.
Copp, David. “Contractarianism and Moral Skepticism.” In Contractarianism and Rational Choice: Essays on David Gauthier’s Morals by Agreement. Edited by Peter Vallentyne, 196–228. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Significant for challenging whether any self-interest based contractarian theory can defeat skepticism because of its constraints and grounding in the expected utility theory of rationality. Outlines problems with connecting the rationality of adopting a moral disposition with the acts it expresses, whether the code that emerges from agreement is a moral one and whether the argument speaks to actual person.
Find this resource:
Copp, David. “The Ring of Gyges: Overridingness and the Unity of Reason.” In Self-Interest. Edited by Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, 86–106. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Important for resurrecting Sidgwick’s view that there is no standard of Reason according to which moral reasons or self-interested reasons are always overriding. Argues that answering the why be moral question is more pressing than answering the why be self-interested question given facts about human psychology and that the former should be answered from the standpoint of self-grounded reason where one best promotes one’s values or desires.
Find this resource:
Copp, David. “The Wrong Answer to an Improper Question?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supp. 33 (2007): 97–130.
DOI: 10.1353/cjp.0.0079Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Makes useful distinction about the why be moral question: (1) whether acting morally makes sense—this assumes that there are moral reasons and asks whether to follow them and (2) whether giving any weight to moral considerations makes sense—this questions the nature of moral reasons and their authority and should explain why an act is wrong. Defends the view that morality is a social code of shared standards.
Find this resource:
Finlay, Stephen. “Too Much Morality.” In Morality and Self-Interest. Edited by Paul Bloomfield, 136–154. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Novel thesis that since morality is radically other-regarding, and self-interest has to do with one’s life going well over its course, the requirements of morality and of self-interest are too excessive and there is no clear answer as to which overrides the other. Having an all-things-considered preference for one over the other is decisive.
Find this resource:
Garner, Richard. “Abolishing Morality.” In Special Issue: Moral Skepticism: 30 Years of Inventing Right and Wrong. Edited by Richard Joyce and Simon Kirchin. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10.5. (2007): 499–513.
DOI: 10.1007/s10677-007-9085-3Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Takes up Mackie’s error theory and argues that it is best for error theorists to abolish morality and moral language because it is fictional. At best, we have moral thoughts but not beliefs, though it is unlikely that they move us to act morally and they are too costly to our integrity to maintain because they are fictional.
Find this resource:
Kavka, Gregory S. “The Reconciliation Project.” In Morality, Reason and Truth: New Essays on the Foundations of Ethics. Edited by David Copp and David Zimmerman, 297–319. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld, 1984.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Novel for reducing the skeptical challenge along four dimensions: audience, agent, social, object. Argues that we need not show that every morally required act is rationally required and that we need to address the puzzled ordinary person who is willing to listen. Proposes the Wider Reconciliation Project according to which it is normally prudent to be moral but sometimes rational to be moral even if not prudent.
Find this resource:
Sterba, James P. Morality: The Why and the What of It. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Reconstrues the skeptic’s position in a way that invokes non-question-begging reasons. Defends “morality as compromise,” according to which moral reasons are seen as a compromise between egoistic or self-interested reasons that the skeptic endorses and altruistic reasons, according to which each person ought to do what best serves the overall interest of others. Morality is compromise because it includes requirements for both self-regard and a constraint on the pursuit of self-interest.
Find this resource:
Superson, Anita. The Moral Skeptic. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195376623.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Unique in expanding the skeptic’s challenge that we demonstrate that every morally required action is in one’s self-interest to capture many more immoralities than self-interested action, especially those perpetuating women’s oppression, thereby nuancing the skepticism project to political concerns. Argues that a successful defeat of the skeptic requires demonstrating that, on grounds of consistency, one not disrespect others’ humanity by privileging oneself and one’s reasons over another and his or her reasons.
Find this resource:
Superson, Anita M. “Standards of Rationality and the Challenge of the Moral Skeptic.” In Out from the Shadows: Analytical Feminist Contributions to Traditional Philosophy. Edited by Sharon L. Crasnow and Anita M. Superson, 139–173. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199855469.003.0007Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Examines two models for asking and answering “Why be moral?” The Hobbesian model allows the privileged to ask why participate in a system requiring self-sacrifice; the Kantian allows the nonprivileged to ask why participate in a system that harms them. Argues for a combination and envisions a fuller model of practical reason and a robust model of ideal rational agency to inform the position of the skeptic. Novel for approaching the skeptical challenge in line with feminist aims.
Find this resource:
Objections to the Skeptic’s Position
Traditionally, the skeptic is defined as endorsing the expected utility theory of rational choice and action, according to which rational action is taken to be action that maximizes the agent’s expected utility, or, the satisfaction of the agent’s interests, desires, or preferences. In order to defeat the skeptic, it must be shown that practical reason dictates acting in morally required ways, even when doing so is against the agent’s self-interest, defined as maximal desire or preference satisfaction. Philosophers have challenged this theory, and if it turns out to be flawed, its failure casts doubt on whether it should be the starting point of the skeptic. Anderson 1993 challenges whether expected utility is the best theory of rational choice and action. Morse 1997 argues for a more complex view of self-interest than mere preference satisfaction. Anderson 2002 and Cudd 2002 examine whether expected utility theory is compatible with feminist aims, with Cudd arguing more favorably in support of it. Superson 2009 questions whether desires deformed by patriarchy count as rational on expected utility theory and, despite the strengths of the theory, rejects it as the skeptic’s starting point. Hampton 1993, however, stresses the importance of promoting self-interest for feminist reasons, which may be a point in favor of expected utility theory.
Anderson, Elizabeth. Value in Ethics and Economics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Sustained examination of the problems with the expected utility theory of rational choice. Detailed defense of a pluralistic expressive theory of value for which desiring is not the only kind of valuing. Defends the theory in terms of questioning whether certain goods can be treated as market commodities. Argues against the commodification of women’s bodies in prostitution, pornography, and surrogacy. Acknowledges the effect of the role of desires deformed by patriarchy on rational choice theory.
Find this resource:
Anderson, Elizabeth. “Should Feminists Reject Rational Choice Theory?” In A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity. 2d ed. Edited by Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt, 369–397. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed and thorough examination of the compatibility of expected utility theory and feminism. Favors the rhetorical version of the theory that purports to explain behavior but takes the ideal rational agent to have stereotypical male qualities. Examines pros and cons of this view of rational agency for feminism.
Find this resource:
Cudd, Ann E. “Rational Choice Theory and the Lessons of Feminism.” In A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity. 2d ed. Edited by Louise M. Antony and Charlotte E. Witt, 398–417. Boulder, CO: Westview, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed analysis of how feminist theory can show the usefulness of rational choice theory, despite the rejection of the latter by some feminists on the grounds that it privileges the status quo in political and social policymaking and has a masculine conception of rationality. Defends rational choice theory as a way to model ideal ways of being and social change, showing that it is not rational for women to give care unless care is reciprocated.
Find this resource:
Hampton, Jean. “Selflessness and the Loss of Self.” In Altruism. Edited by Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, 135–165. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Important for acknowledging that acting self-interestedly is sometimes morally required in order to avoid losing one’s self by being too self-sacrificial. Argues that morality requires service to others only when it is grounded in authentically defined preferences by one who pursues the satisfaction of one’s objective needs that all humans have and sees oneself as having intrinsic and equal value as a human being.
Find this resource:
Morse, Jennifer Roback. “Who Is Rational Economic Man?” In Self-Interest. Edited by Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, 179–206. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that the economists’ view of rational agency that persons act rationally by maximizing on their preferences in full knowledge of them is incomplete. Argues for a more complex view of the self that includes reflective preferences, as well as Longings, which are desires for ultimate goods defining a person. Significant for accounting for our being rational in placing appropriate weight on Longings even when they conflict with satisfying appetites.
Find this resource:
Superson, Anita. The Moral Skeptic. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195376623.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed defense of a model of rationality grounded in consistency rather than self-interest. Defines consistency as coherence between an agent’s reasons for adopting a moral disposition, the argument for the moral theory or principles the agent adopts, the agent’s reasons for acting, and the agent’s desire to be a moral person as reflected in the maxim the agent adopts. Analyzes the effect of desires deformed by patriarchy on expected utility theory and defeating skepticism.
Find this resource:
Amoralism and the Internalism/Externalism Debate
The amoralist recognizes that there is a reason to act morally but denies the force of moral reasons. Some internalists, called motivational internalists, believe that amoralism is not a tenable position because the amoralist is either inconceivable, irrational, or simply lacks a reason to act morally. Motivational internalists take there to be a necessary connection between moral reasons and motivation. Brink 1986 is an externalist who defends the possibility of a sincere amoralist. Internalists Korsgaard 1986 and Smith 1994, the latter responding to Brink 1986, argue against the possibility of a rational amoralist. Superson 2009 responds to Korsgaard 1986 and Smith 1994 and defends weak externalism and the possibility of a rational amoralist but argues that even if we do not defeat the amoralist, we will not have failed to defeat skepticism, because whether one is motivated by a reason is a psychological, not a philosophical, reason. Van Roojen 2010 responds to Brink 1986 and argues for a way in which rationalism is compatible with internalism, allowing for the possibility of a rational amoralist. Mumm 2015 responds to Smith 1994 and other internalists and attempts to unify the gap between internalists and externalists about the possibility of amoralism.
Brink, David. “Externalist Moral Realism.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 Supp. (1986): 23–41.
DOI: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.1986.tb01594.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Notable for acknowledging the possibility of the sincere amoralist who understands moral considerations but remains unmoved. Distinguishes three kinds of internalism: agent, appraiser, and hybrid. Defends externalism against the charge that it threatens morality by making motivation separate from moral reasons by arguing that internalism threatens morality because lacking a motivation means the agent lacks the reason.
Find this resource:
Korsgaard, Christine M. “Skepticism about Practical Reason.” Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986): 5–25.
DOI: 10.2307/2026464Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Well-known paper defending internalism by arguing that recognizing a moral consideration entails having a motive to act on it but only for a rational agent. On this view, the amoralist is conceivable but irrational. Argues that skepticism about practical reason, or whether reason necessarily motivates, need not entail skepticism about pure practical reason, or whether there is a reason to act morally.
Find this resource:
Mumm, John. “Two Functions of Moral Language.” In Motivational Internalism. Edited by Gunnar Bjӧrnsson, Caj Strandberg, Ragnar Francén Olinder, John Eriksson, and Fredrik Bjӧrklund, 282–297. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199367955.003.0014Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Novel argument attempting to unify the gap between internalists and externalists about the possibility of amoralism. Argues that amoralists can make sincere and competent moral judgments but fail to endorse them and so fail to intend to express reactive attitudes and do not take them to have practical clout, making them illegitimate.
Find this resource:
Smith, Michael. The Moral Problem. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1994.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed defense of neo-Humean internalism that amoralists try to make moral judgments but fail because they do not understand them because they lack the appropriate motivation, like a colorblind person who knows how to use color terms but lacks the concept. Denies the possibility of a rational amoralist who understands moral reasons and remains unmoved by them.
Find this resource:
Superson, Anita M. The Moral Skeptic. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195376623.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues against prominent internalist views by Hume, Korsgaard 1986, and Smith 1994 that we need not address the skeptic who believes that amoralism is tenable and defends a weak externalism according to which recognition of a moral reason does not necessarily motivate. Important for arguing that failure to defeat the amoralist does not mean failure to defeat skepticism.
Find this resource:
Van Roojen, Mark. “Moral Rationalism and Rational Amoralism.” Ethics 120 (2010): 495–525.
DOI: 10.1086/652302Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Responds to the concern in Brink 1986 that a rational amoralist is possible. Argues for a way in which rationalism, the view that the requirements of ethics are requirements of practical reason, is compatible with internalism, the view that moral judgments necessarily motivate, in the face of cases of rational amorality and immorality. Is novel for employing Frege’s Puzzle to show the possibility of not acknowledging moral demands while being rational.
Find this resource:
Authority of Moral Reasons
The authority of moral reasons refers to the categoricity or bindingness of moral reasons. While the issue of practical moral skepticism is about demonstrating the rational requiredness of moral reasons, the issue of the authority of moral reasons is about the “grippedness” of moral reasons, or the way they “take” on our reason; it explains their force. Thus it speaks to the practical side of the why be moral issue. It is a separate issue from motivational internalism, which is the view that reasons for action, including moral reasons, necessarily motivate, at least under certain conditions. The issue of the authority of moral reasons lies with explaining exactly what their force is, locating its source, and showing why moral reasons are special because they have it. Korsgaard 1997 follows Kant and grounds the authority of morality in reflection and our identity as part of humanity. Brink 1992 and Copp 2010, both skeptical about the authority of moral reasons, ground it in rationality such that failure to consider moral reasons is irrational. Brink 1997 distinguishes inescapability, authority, and supremacy of moral reasons and argues that moral reasons are no more special than reasons of prudence. Dreier 2001 believes that moral reasons are not authoritative but that the form of instrumental reasoning is, and the author locates it in what he calls “acceptance” of an argument form. Hampton 1998, in a book the author almost finished before her death, likens the authority of a reason to its compellingness but in the end finds the idea mysterious.
Brink, David O. “A Puzzle about the Rational Authority of Morality.” Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 1–26.
DOI: 10.2307/2214236Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Outlines four individually plausible claims about the rational authority of morality that are mutually inconsistent. Useful for explaining the rational authority of morality as there being a reason to behave in accordance with moral norms such that failure to do so is pro tanto irrational. Rejects Foot’s argument comparing the norms of etiquette to those of morality and defends an externalist response that moral norms are more intimately related to people’s important interests than etiquette.
Find this resource:
Brink, David O. “Kantian Rationalism: Inescapability, Authority, and Supremacy.” In Ethics and Practical Reason. Edited by Garrett Cullity and Berys Gaut, 255–291. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Useful distinction and discussion of the difference between the inescapability, authority, and supremacy of moral requirements as categorical imperatives. Argues that, for Kant, the imperatives of categorical prudence may override the reasons of categorical impartiality, or, morality: one has reason to promote one’s own rational agency as well as reason to promote agency impartially.
Find this resource:
Copp, David. “Normativity, Deliberation, and Queerness.” In A World without Values. Edited by Richard Joyce and Simon Kirchin, 141–164. Philosophical Studies Series 114. New York: Springer, 2010.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Important for examining accounts of the authority of moral reason offered by Mackie, Joyce, Williams, Darwall, and Smith and for postulating “the authoritative reasons proposal,” according to which if a rational person believes he or she has a moral reason to do something, he or she is thereby motivated to do it and disposed such that were he or she to deliberate about what to do, he or she would take into account this reason as counting in favor of doing it.
Find this resource:
Dreier, James. “Humean Doubts about Categorical Imperatives.” In Varieties of Practical Reasoning. Edited by Elijah Millgram, 27–47. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 2001.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Denies the categoricity of moral reasons but defends the categoricity of the form of means/ends or instrumental reasoning. Innovative view that the categoricity lies with “accepting” the argument form, which is just what it is to have a reason such that if one denies an argument form, one does not understand what it is to have a reason.
Find this resource:
Hampton, Jean E. The Authority of Reason. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511625213Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Detailed examination of the authority of reason, which is what it means for a norm to apply to us. Argues that there are objectively authoritative norms in science, making science not as far removed from objectivist moral theories. Examines Kantian, Millian, Humean, and naturalized Kantian accounts to explain the authority of hypothetical imperatives, which is allegedly the same as the force of objective moral reasons.
Find this resource:
Korsgaard, Christine M. “The Authority of Reflection.” In The Sources of Normativity. Edited by Onora O’Neill, 90–130. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Important for showing that reason—having a reason to live and act—is the source of obligation which stems from our identity as human beings. Argues that our moral identity is inescapable and governs other identities that we have in terms of our social roles but that moral obligations need not always trump other reasons for action. Our autonomous, reflective nature commands us to act in ways we deem good in terms of our identity.
Find this resource:
Article
- A Priori Knowledge
- Abduction and Explanatory Reasoning
- Ability
- Abortion
- Abstract Objects
- Action
- Addams, Jane
- Adorno, Theodor
- Aesthetic Hedonism
- Aesthetics, Analytic Approaches to
- Aesthetics, Continental
- Aesthetics, Environmental
- Aesthetics, History of
- African Philosophy, Contemporary
- Alexander, Samuel
- Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
- Anarchism, Philosophical
- Animal Rights
- Anscombe, G. E. M.
- Anthropic Principle, The
- Applied Ethics
- Aquinas, Thomas
- Argument Mapping
- Art and Emotion
- Art and Knowledge
- Art and Morality
- Artifacts
- Assertion
- Astell, Mary
- Atheism
- Augustine
- Aurelius, Marcus
- Austin, J. L.
- Autonomy
- Bacon, Francis
- Bayesianism
- Beauty
- Belief
- Bergson, Henri
- Berkeley, George
- Biology, Philosophy of
- Bolzano, Bernard
- Boredom, Philosophy of
- British Idealism
- Buber, Martin
- Buddhist Philosophy
- Burge, Tyler
- Business Ethics
- Camus, Albert
- Canterbury, Anselm of
- Carnap, Rudolf
- Causation
- Cavendish, Margaret
- Certainty
- Chemistry, Philosophy of
- Childhood, Philosophy of
- Chinese Philosophy
- Cognitive Ability
- Cognitive Phenomenology
- Cognitive Science, Philosophy of
- Coherentism
- Color
- Communitarianism
- Computational Science
- Computer Science, Philosophy of
- Comte, Auguste
- Concepts
- Conceptual Role Semantics
- Conditionals
- Confirmation
- Confucius
- Connectionism
- Consciousness
- Constructive Empiricism
- Contemporary Hylomorphism
- Contextualism
- Contrastivism
- Cook Wilson, John
- Cosmology, Philosophy of
- Critical Theory
- Culture and Cognition
- Daoism and Philosophy
- Davidson, Donald
- de Beauvoir, Simone
- de Montaigne, Michel
- Death
- Decision Theory
- Deleuze, Gilles
- Democracy
- Depiction
- Derrida, Jacques
- Descartes, René
- Descartes, René: Sensory Representations
- Descriptions
- Dewey, John
- Dialetheism
- Disability
- Disagreement, Epistemology of
- Disjunctivism
- Dispositions
- Doing and Allowing
- du Châtelet, Emilie
- Dummett, Michael
- Dutch Book Arguments
- Early Modern Philosophy, 1600-1750
- Eastern Orthodox Philosophical Thought
- Education, Philosophy of
- Emotion
- Engineering, Philosophy and Ethics of
- Environmental Philosophy
- Epicurus
- Epistemic Basing Relation
- Epistemic Defeat
- Epistemic Injustice
- Epistemic Justification
- Epistemic Philosophy of Logic
- Epistemology
- Epistemology and Active Externalism
- Epistemology, Bayesian
- Epistemology, Feminist
- Epistemology, Internalism and Externalism in
- Epistemology, Moral
- Epistemology of Education
- Ethical Consequentialism
- Ethical Deontology
- Ethical Intuitionism
- Eugenics and Philosophy
- Events, The Philosophy of
- Evidence
- Evidence-Based Medicine, Philosophy of
- Evidential Support Relation In Epistemology, The
- Evil
- Evolutionary Debunking Arguments in Ethics
- Evolutionary Epistemology
- Experimental Philosophy
- Explanations of Religion
- Extended Mind Thesis, The
- Externalism and Internalism in the Philosophy of Mind
- Faith, Conceptions of
- Fatalism
- Feminist Philosophy
- Feyerabend, Paul
- Fichte, Johann Gottlieb
- Fiction
- Fictionalism
- Fictionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Film, Philosophy of
- Foot, Philippa
- Foreknowledge
- Forgiveness
- Formal Epistemology
- Foucault, Michel
- Free Will
- Frege, Gottlob
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg
- Geometry, Epistemology of
- God and Possible Worlds
- God, Arguments for the Existence of
- God, The Existence and Attributes of
- Grice, Paul
- Habermas, Jürgen
- Hart, H. L. A.
- Heaven and Hell
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Aesthetics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Metaphysics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of History
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of Politics
- Heidegger, Martin: Early Works
- Hermeneutics
- Higher Education, Philosophy of
- History, Philosophy of
- Hobbes, Thomas
- Horkheimer, Max
- Human Rights
- Hume, David: Aesthetics
- Hume, David: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Husserl, Edmund
- Idealizations in Science
- Identity in Physics
- Images
- Imagination
- Imagination and Belief
- Impossible Worlds
- Incommensurability in Science
- Indian Philosophy
- Indispensability of Mathematics
- Inductive Reasoning
- Infinitism
- Instruments in Science
- Intellectual Humility
- Intentionality, Collective
- Intuitions
- James, William
- Japanese Philosophy
- Kant and the Laws of Nature
- Kant, Immanuel: Aesthetics and Teleology
- Kant, Immanuel: Ethics
- Kant, Immanuel: Theoretical Philosophy
- Kierkegaard, Søren
- Knowledge
- Knowledge-first Epistemology
- Knowledge-How
- Kuhn, Thomas S.
- Lacan, Jacques
- Lakatos, Imre
- Langer, Susanne
- Language of Thought
- Language, Philosophy of
- Latin American Philosophy
- Laws of Nature
- Legal Epistemology
- Legal Philosophy
- Legal Positivism
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm
- Levinas, Emmanuel
- Lewis, C. I.
- Liberty
- Literature, Philosophy of
- Locke, John
- Locke, John: Identity, Persons, and Personal Identity
- Logic
- Lottery and Preface Paradoxes, The
- Lucretius
- Machiavelli, Niccolò
- Martin Heidegger: Later Works
- Martin Heidegger: Middle Works
- Marx, Karl
- Material Constitution
- Mathematical Explanation
- Mathematical Pluralism
- Mathematical Structuralism
- Mathematics, Ontology of
- Mathematics, Philosophy of
- Mathematics, Visual Thinking in
- McDowell, John
- McTaggart, John
- Meaning of Life, The
- Mechanisms in Science
- Medically Assisted Dying
- Medicine, Contemporary Philosophy of
- Medieval Logic
- Medieval Philosophy
- Memory
- Mental Causation
- Mereology
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice
- Meta-epistemological Skepticism
- Metaepistemology
- Metaethics
- Metametaphysics
- Metaphilosophy
- Metaphor
- Metaphysical Grounding
- Metaphysics, Contemporary
- Metaphysics, Feminist
- Midgley, Mary
- Mill, John Stuart
- Mind, Metaphysics of
- Modal Epistemology
- Modality
- Models and Theories in Science
- Modularity
- Montesquieu
- Moore, G. E.
- Moral Contractualism
- Moral Naturalism and Nonnaturalism
- Moral Responsibility
- Multiculturalism
- Murdoch, Iris
- Music, Analytic Philosophy of
- Nationalism
- Natural Kinds
- Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Naïve Realism
- Neo-Confucianism
- Neuroscience, Philosophy of
- Nietzsche, Friedrich
- Nonexistent Objects
- Normative Ethics
- Normative Foundations, Philosophy of Law:
- Normativity and Social Explanation
- Objectivity
- Occasionalism
- Olfaction
- Ontological Dependence
- Ontology of Art
- Ordinary Objects
- Other Minds
- Pacifism
- Pain
- Panpsychism
- Paradoxes
- Particularism in Ethics
- Pascal, Blaise
- Paternalism
- Patriotism
- Peirce, Charles Sanders
- Perception, Cognition, Action
- Perception, The Problem of
- Perfectionism
- Persistence
- Personal Identity
- Phenomenal Concepts
- Phenomenal Conservatism
- Phenomenology
- Philosophy for Children
- Photography, Analytic Philosophy of
- Physicalism
- Physicalism and Metaphysical Naturalism
- Physics, Experiments in
- Plato
- Plotinus
- Political Epistemology
- Political Obligation
- Political Philosophy
- Popper, Karl
- Pornography and Objectification, Analytic Approaches to
- Practical Knowledge
- Practical Moral Skepticism
- Practical Reason
- Pragmatics
- Pragmatism
- Probabilistic Representations of Belief
- Probability, Interpretations of
- Problem of Divine Hiddenness, The
- Problem of Evil, The
- Propositions
- Psychology, Philosophy of
- Punishment
- Pyrrhonism
- Qualia
- Quietism
- Quine, W. V. O.
- Race
- Racist Jokes
- Rationalism
- Rationality
- Rawls, John: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Realism and Anti-Realism
- Realization
- Reasons in Epistemology
- Reductionism in Biology
- Reference, Theory of
- Reid, Thomas
- Relativism
- Reliabilism
- Religion, Philosophy of
- Religious Belief, Epistemology of
- Religious Experience
- Religious Pluralism
- Ricoeur, Paul
- Rights
- Risk, Philosophy of
- Rorty, Richard
- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques
- Rule-Following
- Russell, Bertrand
- Ryle, Gilbert
- Sartre, Jean-Paul
- Schopenhauer, Arthur
- Science and Religion
- Science, Theoretical Virtues in
- Scientific Explanation
- Scientific Progress
- Scientific Realism
- Scientific Representation
- Scientific Revolutions
- Scotus, Duns
- Self-Knowledge
- Sellars, Wilfrid
- Semantic Externalism
- Semantic Minimalism
- Semiotics
- Seneca
- Senses, The
- Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology
- Singular Thought
- Situated Cognition
- Situationism and Virtue Theory
- Skepticism, Contemporary
- Skepticism, History of
- Slurs, Pejoratives, and Hate Speech
- Smith, Adam: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge
- Social Epistemology
- Social Identity
- Sounds and Auditory Perception
- Space and Time
- Speech Acts
- Spinoza, Baruch
- Stebbing, Susan
- Strawson, P. F.
- Structural Realism
- Suicide
- Supererogation
- Supervenience
- Tarski, Alfred
- Technology, Philosophy of
- Testimony, Epistemology of
- Theoretical Terms in Science
- Thomas Aquinas' Philosophy of Religion
- Thought Experiments
- Time and Tense
- Time Travel
- Toleration
- Torture
- Transcendental Arguments
- Tropes
- Trust
- Truth
- Truth and the Aim of Belief
- Truthmaking
- Turing Test
- Two-Dimensional Semantics
- Understanding
- Uniqueness and Permissiveness in Epistemology
- Utilitarianism
- Vagueness
- Value of Knowledge
- Vienna Circle
- Virtue Epistemology
- Virtue Ethics
- Virtues, Epistemic
- Virtues, Intellectual
- Voluntarism, Doxastic
- War
- Weakness of Will
- Weil, Simone
- Well-Being
- William of Ockham
- Williams, Bernard
- Wisdom
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Early Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Later Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Middle Works
- Wollstonecraft, Mary