Ethical Deontology
- LAST REVIEWED: 14 September 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 15 January 2019
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0383
- LAST REVIEWED: 14 September 2022
- LAST MODIFIED: 15 January 2019
- DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0383
Introduction
Deontology is usually contrasted with consequentialism (and both with virtue ethics). Whereas consequentialists maintain that the right action is determined solely by its consequences, deontologists deny this and hold that the right action is not determined solely by its consequences. This characterization makes room for the important distinction between moderate deontology (or threshold deontology) and absolutism: Absolutists assert that there are exceptionless moral rules or intrinsically wrong actions that are absolutely wrong and may never be performed, whatever the consequences. Moderate deontologists reject exceptionless moral rules or absolutely wrong actions and regard all moral rules as prima facie rules. A further distinction is between agent-centered deontological theories, which focus upon agents’ duties, and patient-centered (or victim-centered) deontological theories, which focus upon people’s rights. Deontology is associated with the following features which play a more or less significant role in different deontological theories: agent-relativity, especially agent-relative constraints (restrictions), options (prerogatives) and special obligations; priority of the right over the good; definition of the right independently of the good; priority of honoring values over promoting values; intrinsically wrong actions; absolutely wrong actions and exceptionless moral rules; duty for duty’s sake; pluralism of moral rules; respect of persons; non-instrumentalization of persons; human dignity; inviolable rights. Deontologists also maintain the moral relevance of the following distinctions: positive versus negative duties, doing versus allowing (killing versus letting die; see the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Doing and Allowing.”), and intention versus foresight and unintended side-effects. Famous deontological moral principles are Kant’s Categorical Imperative, the Pauline Principle (“Evil may not be done for the sake of good”), the principle of double effect (see the bibliography on Bibliographien zu Themen der Ethik) and the principle that the end does not always justify the means. Deontology can take many forms, the most important ones are Kant’s and Kantian ethics (see the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Immanuel Kant: Ethics”); Ross’s and Rossian-style moral pluralism, natural law theory, and moral contractualism (see the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Moral Contractualism”); libertarianism (in political philosophy); moral particularism (see the bibliography on Bibliographien zu Themen der Ethik); and principlism (in bioethics). Deontology is also often associated with ethical intuitionism (see the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Ethical Intuitionism”) although not every deontological theory is grounded in moral intuitions.
General Overviews
There is no textbook or book-length general overview on deontology available. Even many ethics textbooks do not have a single chapter on deontology, but instead a chapter on Kant’s or Kantian ethics, and sometimes one or more additional chapters on contractualism, intuitionism, moral pluralism, or natural law theory. Alexander and Moore 2016 is a good introduction to the distinction between agent-centered and victim-centered (patient-centered) deontological theories (not dealt with in the other overviews) and to the main current controversies regarding deontology versus consequentialism. Birnbacher 2003 focuses on the comparison between monistic and pluralistic deontological theories. Hurley 2013 offers a short overview of deontology based on a particular understanding of deontology. Gaus 2001 discusses in the author’s two-part article several proposed definitions and characteristic features of deontology. F. M. Kamm is one of the most important contemporary proponents of deontology and presents in Kamm 2007 a (not always easy to read) introduction to the author’s own (victim-focused) view of deontology. Good introductions to Rossian-style deontology can be found in McNaughton and Rawling 2006 and McNaughton and Rawling 2014. Kagan 1999 goes beyond the previously mentioned overviews and offers a comprehensive but still introductory discussion of several deontological constraints (which he regards as the defining feature of deontology). Timmermann 2015 considers various characterizations of deontology and concludes that the word “deontology” is useless and should be banished.
Alexander, Larry, and Michael Moore. “Deontological Ethics.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2016.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An up-to-date and very detailed overview of deontology with a special focus on the division into agent-centered and victim-centered (patient-centered) deontological theories. (Ross is only mentioned once in passing, and none of the many papers on deontology by David McNaughton and Piers Rawling are mentioned.)
Find this resource:
Birnbacher, Dieter. “Deontologische Ethik.” In Analytische Einführung in die Ethik. By Dieter Birnbacher, 113–172. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2003.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A very clear and detailed introduction to deontology with a special emphasis on the comparison between monistic (Kant and M. G. Singer) and pluralistic deontological theories.
Find this resource:
Gaus, Gerald F. “What Is Deontology. Part One: Orthodox Views.” Journal of Value Inquiry 35 (2001): 27–42.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this two-part article, Gaus discusses several ways of characterizing deontology. The first part is mainly concerned with deontology as nonteleological, nonoptimizing, and as giving the right priority over the good.
Find this resource:
Gaus, Gerald F. “What Is Deontology. Part Two: Reasons to Act.” Journal of Value Inquiry 35 (2001): 179–193.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In the second part, Gaus considers various attempts to distinguish deontology from teleology in terms of different reasons to act. He finally distinguishes ten ways to understand deontology and contends that each deontological theory is deontological only in some of these ways.
Find this resource:
Hurley, Paul. “Deontology.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 1272–1287. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this brief introduction Hurley argues that the common feature of all deontological theories is a special class of deontological reasons which can be described as impartial but not impersonal reasons.
Find this resource:
Kagan, Shelly. Normative Ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An introduction to normative ethics almost exclusively in terms of the opposition between deontological and consequentialist (and teleological) theories. Essential reading for anyone who wants a thorough understanding of the current debate between deontology and consequentialism. Picked with ingenious arguments and written in an engaging style.
Find this resource:
Kamm, F. M. “Nonconsequentialism.” In Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm. By F. M. Kamm, 11–47. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195189698.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This is not so much an overview on deontology in general as an introduction to Kamm’s own view of deontology and her (victim-focused, rights-based) defense of deontological constraints. Much more demanding than the other titles in this section.
Find this resource:
McNaughton, David, and Piers Rawling. “Deontology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Edited by David Copp, 424–458. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Very helpful overview from two authors who have co-authored many articles on deontology in which they defend a Rossian version of deontology.
Find this resource:
McNaughton, David, and Piers Rawling. “Deontology.” In Ethics in Practice. 4th ed. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 37–48. Chichester, UK: Wiley Blackwell, 2014.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Shorter presentation of the authors’ view of deontology than in McNaughton and Rawling 2006.
Find this resource:
Timmermann, Jens. “What’s Wrong with Deontology?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 115 (2015): 75–92.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9264.2015.00385.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This paper is not so much an overview, but rather a critique of the very idea of deontology, based on an overview of different characterizations of deontology. Timmermann argues that supposedly deontological theories have nothing in common except being nonconsequentialist.
Find this resource:
Anthologies
There are only a few anthologies on deontology available. Darwall 2003 is a collection of classical and contemporary readings on deontology. It is the only anthology specifically intended as an introduction to deontology. Haber 1994 contains influential articles in the debate whether there are any intrinsically wrong actions that are also absolutely wrong and may not be performed whatever the consequences. Woodward 2001 is a comprehensive collection of articles on the pros and cons of the principle of double effect, which is of central importance to absolutist deontology. Hooker 2012 contains six unrelated and advanced articles on special topics of deontology. The essays in Oderberg and Laing 1997 address various topics in bioethics with the express aim of offering an alternative approach to the dominating consequentialism. Holderegger and Wolbert 2012 is a of newly written articles on historical and systematic topics in the debate between deontological and teleological ethics in theology and philosophy.
Haber, Joram Graf, ed. Absolutism and its Consequentialist Critics. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Collection of nineteen previously published articles, most of them favoring absolutism or moderate deontology.
Find this resource:
Darwall, Stephen, ed. Deontology. Oxford: Blackwell, 2003.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A short but instructive introduction to the typical features of deontology is followed by five classical selections (from Kant, Price, and Ross) and seven influential selections from contemporary deontologists on constraints and agent-relativity as deontology’s underlying rationale (Robert Nozick, Thomas Nagel, and Stephen Darwall) and on the trolley problem, the doctrine of double effect and on Kant on the right to lie (Thomson, Kamm, Quinn, and Korsgaard).
Find this resource:
Holderegger, Adrian, and Werner Wolbert, eds. Deontologie – Teleologie. Normtheoretische Grundlagen in der Diskussion. Fribourg, Switzerland: Academic Press Fribourg, 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains seventeen newly written articles organized under four headings: concepts and distinctions; state of the art in theological ethics; philosophical positions; and areas of application. A wide-ranging collection on historical and systematic topics.
Find this resource:
Hooker, Brad, ed. Developing Deontology: New Essays in Ethical Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley, 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Although the title of this collection (without an introduction) may suggest otherwise, there is no underlying common theme in these newly written advanced essays from Elizabeth Harman, David Owens, Michael Smith, Philip Stratton-Lake, Peter Vallentyne, and Ralph Wedgwood (published also as a special issue in Ratio 24 [2011]).
Find this resource:
Oderberg, David S., and Jacqueline A. Laing, eds. Human Lives: Critical Essays on Consequentialist Bioethics. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This collection of twelve newly written articles wants to break the dominance of consequentialism (and Peter Singer in particular) in bioethics by criticizing consequentialism and defending an alternative—deontological—way of doing bioethics.
Find this resource:
Woodward, P. A., ed. The Doctrine of Double Effect: Philosophers Debate a Controversial Moral Principle. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The principle of double effect is a key component of absolutist deontology (especially in the natural law tradition) but highly contested and with many difficulties of interpretation. This collection gathers many influential articles and covers the whole spectrum of issues, including a section on applied ethics.
Find this resource:
Historical Sources of Ethical Deontology
The two main historical sources of contemporary ethical deontology are Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) and the British intuitionists H. A. Prichard (1871–1947), E. F. Carritt (1876–1964), W. D. Ross (1877–1971) and C. D. Broad (1887–1971). Another historical source—less important to philosophical ethics in general, although the meanwhile widely discussed principle of double effect and most forms of absolutism are rooted in this tradition—is the Catholic natural law tradition.
Historical Overviews
There are only a few historical overviews available that explicitly discuss deontology, and these cover only the British intuitionists’ version of deontology. Dancy 2003 provides a short account of the British intuitionists and their response to the challenge from emotivism. Hill 1950 contrasts deontological theories from “realistic value theories” under the heading “Intuitive Theories” and presents good summaries of the essential points of Prichard’s, Carritt’s, Broad’s and Ross’s deontological theories. Muirhead 1932 traces the development of ethics in Oxford from Prichard, Carritt and Ross to H. W. B. Joseph. Hurka 2014 is an authoritative and comprehensive history of British moral philosophy from the last quarter of the 19th century to the first half of the 20th century and contains a lot of material on the debates between consequentialists and deontologists. Louden 1996 investigates the history of the word “deontology” in the English language.
Dancy, Jonathan. “From Intuitionism to Emotivism.” In The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870–1945. Edited by Thomas Baldwin, 695–705. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A short account of the internal debates among the British intuitionists, their points of agreement and disagreement with (the consequentialist intuitionist) G. E. Moore and their response to the challenge from emotivism.
Find this resource:
Hill, Thomas English. “Deontological Theories.” In Contemporary Ethical Theories. By Thomas English Hill, 321–347. New York: Macmillan, 1950.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In addition to Prichard, Carritt, Broad, and Ross, this overview also covers the two “religious intuitionists” W. G. DeBurgh and Henri Bergson (who play no role in current deontology).
Find this resource:
Hurka, Thomas. British Ethical Theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199233625.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
History of British moral philosophy from the last quarter of the 19th century to the first half of the 20th century, focusing on Sidgwick, Rashdall, McTaggart, Prichard, Moore, Carritt, Ross, Broad, and Ewing. Since the arguments of these authors are not only recounted, but critically assessed, the book is a genuine contribution to current deontology and not only of historical interest. Especially relevant are the chapters “Consequentialism Versus Deontology” and “Act-Consequentialism, Pluralist Deontology.”
Find this resource:
Louden, Robert B. “Towards a Genealogy of ‘Deontology’.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (1996): 571–592.
DOI: 10.1353/hph.1996.0070Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Explores who first introduced the word “deontology” into the English language. Ironically, it was Jeremy Bentham, the founder of utilitarianism, but the first use of “deontology” in roughly its current meaning is attributed to C. D. Broad.
Find this resource:
Muirhead, John H. Rule and End in Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1932.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An account of the development of ethics in Oxford from Prichard to H. W. B. Joseph with chapters on Prichard (“The ‘Mistake’ of Traditional Moral Philosophy,” “Duty and Interest”), Carritt (“A Deontological Theory of Morals”), and Ross (”The Right and the Good”).
Find this resource:
British Intuitionists—Primary Literature
H. A. Prichard was the leader of the British intuitionists and initiated the birth of contemporary non-Kantian pluralist deontology with his arguments against consequentialism and for the underivability of the right in his famous article “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake” (1912), reprinted in Prichard 2002. Carritt 1928 defends a particularist deontological theory and in Carritt 1947 distinguishes four main types of obligation, but is not much discussed today. Ross 1939 and Ross 2002 have the most elaborated deontological theory and are the main sources and inspirations of today’s non-Kantian pluralist deontology. C. D. Broad is credited for introducing the division between deontological and teleological ethical theories in Broad 1930. He took a “mixed view” to be the most plausible view and argued for a fittingness account of rightness, but has never systematically worked out a moral theory.
Broad, C. D. Five Types of Ethical Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1930.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Exposition and critical discussion of Spinoza, Butler, Hume, Kant, and Sidgwick. On pp. 206 ff. the division into deontological and teleological theories is introduced and further explored until p. 218. On pp. 218–223 and 277–285, Broad states his own mixed view according to which “the rightness or wrongness of an action in a given situation is a function of its fittingness in that situation and its utility in that situation” (p. 221).
Find this resource:
Carritt, E. F. The Theory of Morals. An Introduction to Ethical Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1928.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains (among other things) Carritt’s objections against utilitarianism and Kant’s ethics of “duty for duty’s sake,” his argument that the rightness of acts cannot be deduced from their good consequences, and his particularist view that moral rules cannot help us in determining whether an act is morally right.
Find this resource:
Carritt, E. F. Ethical and Political Thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1947.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains (among other things) Carritt’s objections against hedonistic and agathistic (i.e., ideal) utilitarianism and his own view that we have four “types of obligation” (which are not absolute and can conflict with each other): obligations of (distributive and retributive) justice, obligations of improvement, obligations of beneficence, and obligations of prudence.
Find this resource:
Prichard, H. A. Moral Writings. Edited by Jim MacAdam. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
DOI: 10.1093/0199250197.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This edition is now the standard collection of Prichard’s writings on ethics and replaces Moral Obligation (edited by W. D. Ross, Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1949) and the paperback edition (with one added paper) Moral Obligation and Duty and Interest (edited by J. O. Urmson, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968). Contains Prichard’s most famous article “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake” (1912). Introduction by Jim MacAdam.
Find this resource:
Ross, W. D. Foundations of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1939.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this book Ross is more concerned with metaethical issues and elaborates on topics that have not (sufficiently) been dealt with in Ross 2002, such as naturalistic definitions of “right,” the nature and ground of rightness, the nature of what is right, the knowledge of what is right, the obligation to fulfil promises, the nature of goodness and moral goodness, the psychology of moral action, free will, and Broad’s fittingness account of rightness.
Find this resource:
Ross, W. D. The Right and the Good. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
DOI: 10.1093/0199252653.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Essential reading. Originally published in 1930, this is (besides Kant) the most important source and inspiration of contemporary deontology. Especially the second chapter “What Makes Right Acts Right?” is a must-read, since it contains the gist of Ross’s deontological theory of the right: his arguments against ideal utilitarianism, his pluralistic theory of prima facie duties and his intuitionistic moral epistemology. Subsequent chapters deal with the meaning, nature and content of the good.
Find this resource:
British Intuitionists—Secondary Literature on Carritt and Prichard
The arguments of the British intuitionists’ against ideal utilitarianism are extensively discussed in Shaver 2011, Shaver 2013, and Shaver 2018. Prichard’s arguments are also criticized in Schwarz 1971 who contends that utilitarianism is compatible with Prichard’s view that the right is not derivable from the good. Dancy 2014 provides a critical overview of Prichard’s views in ethics and includes a criticism of Prichard’s objections against Kant. A helpful summary of Prichard’s main theses in ethics can be found in Broad 1950. Carritt is not as important as Prichard for today’s deontology, and there is not much literature on him available. For a short overview of his moral philosophy, one should consult Skelton 2013.
Broad, C. D. “Critical Notice of H. A. Prichard, Moral Obligation (Oxford, 1949).” Mind 59 (1950): 555–566.
DOI: 10.1093/mind/LIX.236.555Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains useful summaries of the main theses of Prichard’s papers “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?” “Green’s Theory of Political Obligation,” “Moral Obligation,” and “The Obligation to Keep a Promise.”
Find this resource:
Dancy, Jonathan. “Harold Arthur Prichard.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2014.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Critical introduction to Prichard’s moral philosophy.
Find this resource:
Schwarz, Stephen D. “Does Prichard’s Essay Rest on a Mistake?” Ethics 81 (1971): 169–180.
DOI: 10.1086/291807Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that in his famous essay Prichard conflates the question why we ought to do our duty with the question what our duty is and that establishing his thesis regarding the first question—that we cannot give any reason why we ought to do our duty—does not require to refute utilitarianism.
Find this resource:
Shaver, Robert. “The Birth of Deontology.” In Underivative Duty. British Moral Philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing. Edited by Thomas Hurka, 126–145. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2011.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577446.003.0008Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Presents and critically discusses Carritt’s and Ross’s arguments against ideal utilitarianism (and, ipso facto, for deontology).
Find this resource:
Shaver, Robert. “Prichard, H. A.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 4072–4078. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Mainly a critical discussion of Prichard’s arguments against consequentialism and for his own view in his famous article “Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?”
Find this resource:
Shaver, Robert. “Prichard’s Arguments against Ideal Utilitarianism.” Utilitas 30 (2018): 54–72.
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820817000048Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A reconstruction and evaluation (as not successful) of Prichard’s various arguments against utilitarianism.
Find this resource:
Skelton, Anthony. “Carritt, E. F.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Short overview of Carritt’s views in metaethics and normative ethics.
Find this resource:
British Intuitionists—Secondary Literature on Ross
There are some very good introductions to Ross’s moral philosophy. Skelton 2012, Stratton-Lake 2002, and Stratton-Lake 2013 cover Ross’s normative ethics and metaethics, whereas Dancy 1991 and Timmons 2013 confine themselves to Ross’s normative ethics. (Timmons’s article is more accessible than Dancy’s.) Blanshard 1961 is very good at conveying the fundamental difference between Rossian deontology and utilitarianism and at highlighting the point where even readers sympathetic to deontology may part company with Ross because “a strong case has been carried too far.” Johnson 1959 is the only book-length study of Ross’s moral philosophy and still well worth reading. In his advanced article, Wiggins 1998 argues that with his prima facie duty to promote the good Ross makes a too great concession to consequentialism. See also Moral Pluralism.
Blanshard, Brand. “Deontology.” In Reason and Goodness. By Brand Blanshard, 139–160. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1961.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A neglected, but highly recommended discussion of Ross’s understanding of deontology. Blanshard conveys clearly the fundamental differences between deontology and utilitarianism. He agrees that rightness is not always based on the goodness of consequences but also on the intrinsic character of the act itself but finds it unbelievable that the intrinsic character of the act has no connection at all to goodness. (Should be read together with McNaughton and Rawling 1992 (cited under Honoring (versus Promoting) Values.)
Find this resource:
Dancy, Jonathan. “An Ethic of Prima Facie Duties.” In A Companion to Ethics. Edited by Peter Singer, 219–229. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An introduction and critique (from a particularist point of view) of Ross’s account of prima facie duties.
Find this resource:
Johnson, Oliver. Rightness and Goodness. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1959.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The only book-length study of Ross’s moral philosophy. A sympathetic presentation and discussion of Rossian deontology by someone who finally rejects it. Contains a discussion of Prichard’s arguments against ideal utilitarianism and of Broad’s and Ross’s fittingness account of rightness.
Find this resource:
Skelton, Anthony. “William David Ross.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A comprehensive introduction to Ross’s moral philosophy.
Find this resource:
Stratton-Lake, Philip. “Introduction.” In The Right and the Good. By W. D. Ross, ix–l. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
DOI: 10.1093/0199252653.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A detailed introduction to Ross’s metaphysics of morals (moral truth and moral realism, simplicity and non-naturalism), normative ethics (critique of consequentialism, other attempts to derive the right from the good, prima facie duties, pluralism about the good), and moral epistemology (self-evidence). Stratton-Lake agrees with most of Ross’s theses and argues that many common criticisms are due to misrepresentations of his views.
Find this resource:
Stratton-Lake, Philip. “Ross, W. D.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 4661–4669. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A sympathetic shorter overview of Ross’s ethics.
Find this resource:
Timmons, Mark. “Moral Pluralism.” In Moral Theory. An Introduction. 2d ed. By Mark Timmons, 245–269. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A first-rate introduction to Ross’s normative ethics. Unlike the other introductions this one does not discuss Ross’s metaethics.
Find this resource:
Wiggins, David. “The Right and the Good and W. D. Ross’s Criticism of Consequentialism.” Utilitas 10 (1998): 261–280.
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820800006208Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this interesting article Wiggins argues that Ross does not completely free himself from Moore’s consequentialism because his prima facie duty to promote the good demotes the other prima facie duties to mere exceptions to this duty. With comments from Jonathan Dancy (“Wiggins and Ross,” pp. 281–85) and Stephen Darwall (“Under Moore’s Spell,” pp. 286–91).
Find this resource:
Immanuel Kant—Primary Literature
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) is the other main historical source of deontological ethics. Central to Kantian deontology is human dignity, the unconditional value of persons and the requirement to treat people as ends in themselves and never merely as means. In contrast to the British intuitionists’ pluralism of moral rules Kant establishes one supreme moral principle—the Categorical Imperative—and does not rely on moral intuitions. His major works on ethics are collected in Kant 1996. For further English and German editions of Kant’s ethical works see section “Kant’s Ethical Works” in the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Immanuel Kant: Ethics.” For a guide through the huge literature on Kant’s ethics, see the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Immanuel Kant: Ethics.” See also Kantian Ethics.
Kant, Immanuel. Practical Philosophy. Translated and edited by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains Kant’s major works on ethics, especially Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785); Critique of Practical Reason (1788); The Metaphysics of Morals (1797); and the famous essay “On a supposed right to lie from philanthropy” (1797), which is the source of Kant’s reputation as an absolutist.
Find this resource:
Immanuel Kant—Deontological Versus Consequentialist Interpretations of Kant’s Ethics
Although Kant’s ethical theory has always been regarded as the paradigm of deontology—the reasons therefore are discussed in Witschen 2012—this received view has been challenged by a number of authors. Some argue that Kant’s ethics doesn’t fit neatly into the classification of ethical theories as either deontological or consequentialist/teleological because his theory lacks some features supposed to be essential of deontology and/or contains elements typical of teleological or consequentialist theories (Herman 1993, Wood 2008). Others (Cummiskey 1996, Hare 1997, Kagan 2002) even argue that Kant’s ethics should or could be interpreted as a consequentialist ethical theory. This interpretation is rejected by Timmermann 2005. Forschler 2013 contends that Timmermann’s arguments rest on a confusion between Kant’s normative ethical deontology and Kant’s metaethical ethical rationalism: Kantian rationalist foundations do not exclude normative consequentialism. The whole convoluted dispute on the classification of Kant’s ethics is systematically treated in Bambauer 2011. See also Kantian Ethics.
Bambauer, Christoph. Deontologie und Teleologie in der kantischen Ethik. Freiburg im Breisgau, Germany: Herder, 2011.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This comprehensive study begins with a general discussion and clarification of the typology of ethical theories into deontological, teleological, consequentialist, and axiological theories and then undertakes a thorough examination of Kant’s ethics with respect to the characteristic features of these types of ethical theory.
Find this resource:
Cummiskey, David. Kantian Consequentialism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
DOI: 10.1093/0195094530.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that Kant’s formula of humanity as end in itself, which requires to treat people as ends rather than as mere means, generates consequentialism.
Find this resource:
Forschler, Scott. “Kantian and Consequentialist Ethics: The Gap Can Be Bridged.” Metaphilosophy 44 (2013): 88–104.
DOI: 10.1111/meta.12015Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues (against Timmermann 2005) that in interpreting Kant’s ethics one has to distinguish between normative ethical deontology and metaethical ethical rationalism. Metaethical ethical rationalism does not imply normative ethical deontology, and Kant is like Hare, an ethical rationalist, but, unlike Hare, a normative deontologist.
Find this resource:
Hare, R. M. “Could Kant Have Been a Utilitarian?” In Sorting Out Ethics. By R. M. Hare, 147–165. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Revised version of the article originally published in 1993. Argues that Kant could have been a utilitarian because his requirement to treat other people’s ends as one’s own ends leads directly to utilitarianism.
Find this resource:
Herman, Barbara. “Leaving Deontology Behind.” In The Practice of Moral Judgment. By Barbara Herman, 208–240. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Stresses the importance of a conception of value in Kant’s ethical theory and contends that if it is characteristic of deontology that the right has absolute priority over the good in the sense that all considerations of value are subordinated to principles of right and duty, then Kant’s ethics is not deontological.
Find this resource:
Kagan, Shelly. “Kantianism for Consequentialists.” In Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Allen W. Wood and Immanuel Kant, 111–156. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that Kant’s formula of universal law does not generate deontological constraints but requires that agents do the act with the best consequences.
Find this resource:
Timmermann, Jens. “Why Kant Could not Have Been a Utilitarian.” Utilitas 17 (2005): 243–264.
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820805001639Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues against Hare that Kant could not have been a utilitarian. Timmermann’s arguments are disputed by Forschler 2013.
Find this resource:
Witschen, Dieter. “Warum gilt Kant als Erzdeontologe? Ein Spektrum von Gründen.” In Deontologie – Teleologie. Normtheoretische Grundlagen in der Diskussion. Edited by Adrian Holderegger and Werner Wolbert, 227–247. Fribourg, Switzerland: Academic Press Fribourg, 2012.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Explores the reasons why Kant’s ethics is typically regarded as the paradigm of deontology. The following four reasons are identified and discussed: priority of the right over the good, unconditional duty, Categorical Imperative, and absolutist (“strict deontological”) justification of moral norms.
Find this resource:
Wood, Allen. “Kantian Ethics vs. ‘Consequentialism.’” In Kantian Ethics. By Allen W. Wood, 259–269. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2008.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Thoughtful considerations on why the supposedly strict opposition between Kantian ethics and consequentialism is an oversimplification.
Find this resource:
Agent-relativity
Agent-relativity is often taken to be a defining feature of deontology in contrast to agent-neutral consequentialism: Agent-relative constraints prohibit that I kill someone; agent-relative options (prerogatives) allow me to pursue my own projects even if they have no agent-neutral value and even if I thereby do not maximize the good; agent relative special obligations are commitments to persons due to their relationship with me. Conceiving deontology and consequentialism in terms of agent-relativity and agent-neutrality is of relatively recent origin—the terms (but not the idea behind them) were introduced in Derek Parfits’s Reasons and Persons (1984). Meanwhile the distinction is understood (and formalized) in many different ways, which are helpfully explained in Jollimore 2001, McNaughton and Rawling 1991, and Ridge 2017. Before reading these advanced articles one should read Nagel 1986 to get an impression of why the idea of agent-relativity is so important for deontology and at the same time so difficult to make sense of. See also Constraints and the Paradox of Deontology.
Jollimore, Troy A. “Three Accounts of Agent-Relativity.” In Friendship and Agent-Relative Morality. By Troy A. Jollimore, 117–139. New York: Garland, 2001.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This chapter explains, compares, and evaluates the following three accounts of agent-relativity: Amartya Sen’s relativity of permissibility, Thomas Nagel’s relativity of reasons, and David McNaughton’s and Piers Rawling’s relativity of principles. Jollimore rejects all three accounts and in the subsequent chapter defends his own “moral preferability account.”
Find this resource:
McNaughton, David, and Piers Rawling. “Agent-Relativity and the Doing-Happening Distinction.” Philosophical Studies 63 (1991): 167–185.
DOI: 10.1007/BF00381686Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The authors evaluate the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction drawn by Nagel, Parfit, Pettit, and Sen and develop their own account of the distinction.
Find this resource:
Nagel, Thomas. “Ethics.” In The View from Nowhere. By Thomas Nagel, 164–188. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Reprinted as “Agent-Relativity and Deontology” in Darwall 2003 (cited under Anthologies). A fascinating account of agent-relativity and the puzzling nature of agent-relative constraints (based on Nagel’s Tanner Lectures, published in 1980).
Find this resource:
Ridge, Michael. “Reasons for Action: Agent-Neutral vs. Agent-Relative.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2017.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A very helpful explanation of the various interpretations of the agent-neutral/agent-relative distinction and its relevance (Section 6: “Why the Distinction Matters”) to deontology.
Find this resource:
Constraints and the Paradox of Deontology
Deontological constraints (restrictions, side-constraints) are agent-relative prohibitions, which may not be violated, even if their violation would have better consequences than obeying them and even if a single violation of a constraint would minimize the total number of violations of that same constraint: You may not kill someone even if that is the only way to prevent someone from killing two. Constraints are the essential feature of deontology and account for its intuitive appeal. So much the worse that they seem to be paradoxical or irrational: if killing is morally wrong, isn’t it irrational to allow more killings to happen instead of minimizing them? This so-called paradox of deontology is widely regarded as the most serious objection to deontology and has generated a huge body of literature. To quickly get a vivid idea of what is so puzzling about constraints one should read Kagan 1989 (pp. 27–32). Kagan 1999 is the best introduction to constraints and the most accessible text. A very brief and more difficult introduction to the paradox of deontology is provided by Hurley 2013. A classic and must-read on constraints is Scheffler 1994 who set the terms for the debate with his sharp arguments against constraints. Famous (patient-based) defenses of constraints building on the value of inviolability are Kamm 1995 and Nagel 2008. Lippert-Rasmussen 1999 evaluates different accounts of why constraints are puzzling and criticizes Kamm’s and Nagel’s defense of constraints. Kamm’s defense of deontology in Kamm 2007 is essential reading for anyone seriously interested in deontology (but due to its extreme difficulty, can only be recommended to those with a very serious interest). Chappell 2014 and Heuer 2011 are two recent attempts to dissolve the paradox of deontology.
Chappell, Timothy. “Intuition, System, and the ‘Paradox’ of Deontology.” In Knowing What To Do. Imagination, Virtue, and Platonism in Ethics. By Timothy Chappell, 60–79. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
According to Chappell the “paradox” is a contradiction that results from the assumptions “that it is the role of agency to produce goodness, and that it is good to respect constraints” (p. 66). The solution is to reject the first (consequentialist) assumption: although it is one role of agency to produce goodness, it is not its only role. The rationality of agency therefore need not be assessed only by the criterion of productiveness of good.
Find this resource:
Heuer, Ulrike. “The Paradox of Deontology, Revisited.” In Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 1. Edited by Mark Timmons, 236–267. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that there is no paradox resulting from the general structure of deontological constraints, because constraints involve “personal reasons” to comply with them but do not imply reasons to prevent others from violating them. But since there may be other (nonpersonal) reasons (e.g., to help someone), which may outweigh constraints and therefore allow the violation of constraints, deontology is still saddled with the problem of determining when constraints may be violated.
Find this resource:
Hurley, Paul. “Paradox of Deontology.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 3790–3794. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A short and clearly written introductory article. According to Hurley, the paradox of deontology can be dissolved if one rejects the teleological theory of value.
Find this resource:
Kagan, Shelly. “Constraints.” In The Limits of Morality. By Shelly Kagan, 24–32. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The whole of the book is a rigorous case for consequentialism and against constraints and options. On pp. 27–32 Kagan vividly illustrates why consequentialists regard the defense of constraints as hopeless: he dismisses five attempts to justify the constraint against killing one to save two as failing to give even the beginnings of an explanation. These few pages give a vivid impression of why constraints are so widely considered to be paradoxical.
Find this resource:
Kagan, Shelly. “‘Doing Harm’ and ‘Other Constraints.’” In Normative Ethics. By Shelly Kagan, 70–152. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The best starting point for getting acquainted with constraints and their difficulties. A clear, rigorous, and ingenious discussion of doing harm, doing and allowing, intending harm, lying, promises, special obligations, duties to oneself, and thresholds for constraints (which are required by nonabsolutist deontological theories). Fair presentation of constraints by a consequentialist.
Find this resource:
Kamm, F. M. “Inviolability.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20 (1995): 165–175.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1475-4975.1995.tb00310.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A short and reasonably accessible article, explaining how the value of (persons’) inviolability can justify constraints.
Find this resource:
Kamm, F. M. Intricate Ethics: Rights, Responsibilities, and Permissible Harm. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195189698.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
One of the most important (and certainly most difficult) books on deontology. Kamm is known for her method of arguing with a painstaking analysis of lots of slightly different examples. Extremely demanding reading. Contains sixteen revised essays on various topics (including the trolley problem and the doctrine of double effect), which together amount to a forceful defense of deontological constraints.
Find this resource:
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. “In What Way Are Constraints Paradoxical?” Utilitas 11 (1999): 49–70.
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820800002260Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An advanced article that discusses different accounts (by Nozick, Scheffler, Kamm, and Nagel) of why constraints are paradoxical and criticizes Kamm’s and Nagel’s defense of constraints (in terms of the inviolability of persons).
Find this resource:
Nagel, Thomas. “The Value of Inviolability.” In Morality and Self-Interest. Edited by Paul Bloomfield, 102–113. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
English version of a paper originally published 1994 in French. Building on Kamm’s idea of inviolability Nagel argues that the impersonal value of inviolability can justify deontological constraints (interpreted as noninstrumental rights).
Find this resource:
Scheffler, Samuel. The Rejection of Consequentialism. A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions. Rev. ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
DOI: 10.1093/0198235119.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First edition, 1982. Scheffler was the first to systematically discuss deontological constraints. Because his sustained attack on constraints shaped the subsequent debate this book is a must-read. The revised edition contains three previously published essays which deal with objections from Foot, Bennett, and Kagan. The response to Foot in “Agent-Centred Restrictions, Rationality, and the Virtues” (Mind new series 94.375 (1985): pp. 409–419) is especially recommended.
Find this resource:
Priority of the Right over the Good
The slogan that in deontology the right is prior to the good is very popular but it has to be used with care because there is no single conception of the priority of the right. Among its different meanings are the following: The right is independent of values, the good and the pursuit of the good; the right is not defined instrumentally as the maximization of the good; the principles of the right do not presuppose principles of the good; the right constrains the good; the good is not defined independently of the right; morality is a system of categorical imperatives. The idea of the priority of the right over the good is attributed to Kant 1996 but was made prominent by Rawls 1999 when Rawls claimed that the structure of an ethical theory is determined by the definition and the relationship of the right and the good: In teleological theories, the good is defined independently of the right whereas in deontological theories the right has priority over the good because the right constrains the good and the good is not defined independently of the right. Rawls 2005 explains how the priority of the right figures in the author’s theory of justice as fairness. Kymlicka 1989 argues that there is no real issue about whether the right or the good has priority and that Rawls’s contrast between teleology and deontology in terms of the priority of the right is based on a confusion. Freeman 2007 defends and explains in detail Rawls idea of the priority of the right and argues that it is Kymlicka, not Rawls, who is confused about the distinction between teleology and deontology. Larmore 1996 argues for a different conception of the priority of the right, according to which the priority of the right means that morality is a system of categorical imperatives and is characteristic of both consequentialism/utilitarianism and deontology in contrast to the priority of the good in virtue ethics.
Freeman, Samuel. “Utilitarianism, Deontology and the Priority of the Right.” In Justice and the Social Contract. Essays on Rawlsian Political Philosophy. By Samuel Freeman, 45–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Originally published 1994. Extensive interpretation and clarification of Rawls’s idea of the priority of the right. Defends Rawls against Kymlicka 1989 and argues that the priority of the right must not be confused with deontology.
Find this resource:
Kant, Immanuel. “The Analytic of Practical Reason. Chapter II: On the Concept of an Object of Pure Practical Reason.” In Critque of Practical Reason. By Immanuel Kant. Edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor, 186–194. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Originally published 1788. The locus classicus of the idea of the priority of the right where Kant asserts “that the concept of good and evil must not be determined before the moral law . . . but only (as was done here) after it and by means of it” (p. 190). Difficult reading. Prussian Academy pagination 5:57–67.
Find this resource:
Kymlicka, Will. “The Right and the Good.” In Liberalism, Community and Culture. By Will Kymlicka, 21–43. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Criticizes Rawls’s distinction between utilitarianism and deontology, because according to Kymlicka, there are two forms of utilitarianism, an utterly implausible teleological one in which the good is prior to the right and a more compelling (but still implausible) nonteleological one. In nonteleological utilitarianism, the right is not defined as the maximization of the good; rather, the maximization of the good follows from each individual’s claim to equal consideration.
Find this resource:
Larmore, Charles. “The Right and the Good.” In The Morals of Modernity. By Charles Larmore, 19–40. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Larmore argues that the priority of the right over the good does not distinguish deontology from consequentialism. The priority of the right means that morality is a system of categorical imperatives and duty is independent of the agent’s own good, and this is true of both deontology and consequentialism, and, more general, of modern ethics in contrast to ancient ethics or virtue ethics.
Find this resource:
Rawls, John. “‘Classical Utilitarianism’ and ‘Some Related Contrasts.’” In A Theory of Justice. Revised Edition. By John Rawls, 19–30. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First edition 1971. In these sections from A Theory of Justice Rawls distinguishes utilitarianism as a teleological theory from his theory of “justice as fairness” as a deontological theory: in teleological theories, the good has priority over the right, in justice as fairness the right is prior to the good because it constrains the permissible conceptions of the good and is not defined as the maximization of the good.
Find this resource:
Rawls, John. “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good.” In Political Liberalism. Exp. ed. By John Rawls, 173–211. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Originally published in 1988. Explains in detail the meaning and the central role of the priority of the right in “justice as fairness.” The chapter is concerned (more than Rawls 1999) with political philosophy and the conceptions of the good that are compatible with the priority of the right. Essential for understanding the priority of the right in political philosophy but not so much for understanding ethical deontology versus consequentialism.
Find this resource:
Honoring (versus Promoting) Values
The distinction between promoting and honoring values is a further attempt to distinguish consequentialism from deontology. It was introduced in Pettit 1991, further explained in Pettit 1997, and has been criticized by McNaughton and Rawling 1992.
McNaughton, David, and Piers Rawling. “Honoring and Promoting Values.” Ethics 102 (1992): 835–843.
DOI: 10.1086/293451Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
McNaughton and Rawling reject Pettit’s approach of characterizing ethical theories in terms of the proper response to values, because on their Rossian version of deontology the right is independent from the good and our duties should not be interpreted as a response to values.
Find this resource:
Pettit, Philip. “Consequentialism.” In A Companion to Ethics. Edited by Peter Singer, 230–240. Oxford: Blackwell, 1991.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that consequentialists and deontologists have different views on the proper response to values: Consequentialists think that the proper response to values is to promote them, whereas deontologists think the proper response is that agents honor values in their own lives even if this fails to promote their general realization. Pettit thinks that promoting values is more rational and results in a much simpler ethical theory.
Find this resource:
Pettit, Philip. “Value Theories.” In The Consequentialist Perspective. By Philip Pettit, 92–174, 124–133. Three Methods of Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A more detailed account of the honoring/promoting-distinction.
Find this resource:
Forms of Deontology
Ethical deontology can take many different forms. A basic distinction is between absolutist and moderate deontology. Absolutists hold that there are some kinds of intrinsically wrong actions that are absolutely wrong—wrong in any circumstances and whatever the consequences of not performing them. Moderate deontologists deny this and hold that intrinsically wrong actions may be performed to avert sufficiently bad consequences. According to their historical roots three forms of deontology can be distinguished: Natural law theory is an absolutist deontology that goes back to Thomas Aquinas. Moral pluralism is a moderate deontology inspired by the British Intuitionists and especially by W. D. Ross. Kantian ethics can be absolutist as well as moderate and comprises Kant’s ethics and its defenders and Kant-inspired forms of deontology such as contractualism.
Absolutism
Absolutists maintain that there are absolute constraints or, in other words, there are some kinds of intrinsically wrong actions that are absolutely wrong—wrong in any circumstances and whatever the consequences of not performing them. Absolutism is an extreme form of deontology that is often attributed to Kant 1996 and is characteristic of the Catholic natural law tradition. Most contemporary deontologists are moderate deontologists who hold that intrinsically wrong actions are only prima facie wrong and that there are thresholds to constraints. Contemporary proponents (or at least friends of) absolutism include G. E. M. Anscombe, J. Boyle, A. Donagan, J. Finnis, Ch. Fried, P. Geach, A. Gewirth, G. Grisez, and Th. Nagel. Boyle 2009 and Robinson 2013 provide helpful short introductions to absolutism. Haber 1994 contains the most influential articles and is essential reading for understanding absolutism. Finnis 1991 argues for absolutism from the standpoint of Catholic natural law theory, whereas Denyer 2004 and Fried 1978 attempt a non-religious defense of absolutism. A good example of how to justify the absolute prohibition on lying within natural law theory is provided by Murphy 1996. See also Natural Law Theory and Moderate Deontology (Threshold Deontology).
Boyle, Joseph. “Exceptionless Rule Approaches.” In A Companion to Bioethics. 2d ed. Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer, 77–84. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Good Explanation of the idea of exceptionless rules and their application in moral thinking. Although Boyle belongs to the Catholic natural law tradition, he wants to get across that absolutism can be justified independently of theistic premises.
Find this resource:
Denyer, Nicholas. “Is Anything Absolutely Wrong?” In Human Values. New Essays on Ethics and Natural Law. Edited by David S. Oderberg and Timothy Chappell, 39–57. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Clarification and defense of absolutism.
Find this resource:
Finnis, John. Moral Absolutes. Tradition, Revision, and Truth. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1991.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In these four lectures Finnis, an eminent figure in the Catholic natural law tradition, uses philosophical and theological arguments to defend the Christian view of exceptionless moral rules.
Find this resource:
Fried, Charles. Right and Wrong. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978.
DOI: 10.4159/harvard.9780674332508Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Fried defends (mainly by relying on his intuitions) absolute rules but concedes that in catastrophic cases the absoluteness of right and wrong may “yield” but then the categories of right and wrong do no longer apply.
Find this resource:
Haber, Joram Graf, ed. Absolutism and Its Consequentialist Critics. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Collection of nineteen previously published articles from prominent participants in the debate between absolutism and consequentialism. The authors are G. E. M. Anscombe, Jonathan Bennett, R. B. Brandt, A. Donagan, Ph. Foot, R. G. Frey, Ch. Fried, P. Geach, A. Gewirth, G. Grisez, R. Shaw, St. Hampshire, R. M. Hare, I. Kant, Th. Nagel, K. Nielsen, J. Rachels, and B. Williams.
Find this resource:
Kant, Immanuel. “On a Supposed Right to Lie from Philanthropy.” In Practical Philosophy. By Immanuel Kant. Translated and edited by Mary J. Gregor, 611–615. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Originally published 1797. Kant’s famous essay in which he holds that it is wrong to lie to prevent the murder of an innocent. Prussian Academy pagination 8:425–430.
Find this resource:
Murphy, Mark C. “Natural Law and the Moral Absolute Against Lying.” American Journal of Jurisprudence 41 (1996): 81–101.
DOI: 10.1093/ajj/41.1.81Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that lying is absolutely morally forbidden because it violates the good of practical reasonableness.
Find this resource:
Robinson, Luke. “Moral Absolutes.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 3316–3322. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Concise overview, particularly good at pointing to possible misunderstandings of absolutism.
Find this resource:
Moderate Deontology (Threshold Deontology)
Moderate deontologists (threshold deontologists) are opposed to absolutism (absolutist deontology) and hold that an intrinsically wrong act may be performed in order to avert sufficiently bad (horrible) consequences. (They remain deontologists because for consequentialists it would suffice to avert slightly worse consequences.) Since most deontologists are moderate deontologists this section lists only titles that explicitly discuss the advantages and disadvantages of moderate (threshold) deontology. A very readable introductory chapter is Kagan 1999. (Kagan is the only consequentialist among the authors of this section). Thresholds are defended in Brennan 1995, Thomson 1990, Zamir and Medina 2008, and Zamir and Medina 2010. Critics are Alexander 2000, Ellis 1992, and Wonnell 2011. Brennan 2009 extends the usual discussion of thresholds for constraints and rights to thresholds for options and their relationship to thresholds for rights. See also Absolutism.
Alexander, Larry. “Deontology at the Threshold.” San Diego Law Review 37 (2000): 893–912.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Confronts threshold deontology with a series of puzzles and problems.
Find this resource:
Brennan, Samantha. “A Threshold for Rights.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 33 (1995): 143–168.
DOI: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.1995.tb00737.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Offers in the first part a defense of thresholds for rights (by analyzing the structure of thresholds into three components: a total requirement, an existential constraint and a universal constraint) and criticizes in the second part the view of Thomson 1990 who also defends thresholds but rejects aggregation across people.
Find this resource:
Brennan, Samantha. “Moderate Deontology and Moral Gaps.” Philosophical Perspectives 23.1 (2009): 23–43.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1520-8583.2009.00160.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
An interesting article on the relationship between thresholds for options (prerogatives) and thresholds for rights.
Find this resource:
Ellis, Anthony. “Deontology, Incommensurability and the Arbitrary.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992): 855–875.
DOI: 10.2307/2107914Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that nonabsolutist deontology is untenable because it is impossible to nonarbitrarily specify a “cut-off point” where the consequences are sufficiently bad to allow an intrinsically wrong act.
Find this resource:
Kagan, Shelly. “Thresholds.” In Normative Ethics. By Shelly Kagan, 78–84. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1999.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Brief introduction to the difficulties of moderate deontology.
Find this resource:
Thomson, Judith Jarvis. “Tradeoffs.” In The Realm of Rights. By Judith Jarvis Thomson, 149–175. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Thomson defends thresholds for rights but holds that some rights (e.g., the right not to be killed) are maximally stringent, because (according to Thomson’s high-threshold thesis) “where claims are concerned, the numbers do not count” (p. 167); that is, aggregation across people is not allowed.
Find this resource:
Wonnell, Christopher T. “Deontology, Thresholds, and Efficiency.” Legal Theory 17 (2011): 301–317.
DOI: 10.1017/S1352325211000176Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A forceful critique of Zamir and Medina 2010.
Find this resource:
Zamir, Eyal, and Barak Medina. “Law, Morality, and Economics: Integrating Moral Constraints with Economic Analysis of Law.” California Law Review 96 (2008): 323–391.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Extensive discussion and defense of threshold deontology with illustrations from welfare economics and law.
Find this resource:
Zamir, Eyal, and Barak Medina. Law, Economics, and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195372168.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A thorough book-length defense of threshold deontology with (in the second part) detailed applications to the fight against terrorism, antidiscrimination law, contract law and legal paternalism. Especially relevant is the chapter “Threshold Deontology and Its Critique” (pp. 41–56).
Find this resource:
Natural Law Theory
Natural law ethics is a distinctive form of deontology with its own tradition going back to Aquinas as the most important historical source. Because it belongs to the Catholic tradition of moral philosophy, it has been largely neglected in philosophical ethics. The distinctive feature of natural law theory is that the right (the moral rules) is derived from the good (i.e., a list of basic human goods) and a principle of practical rationality. It is therefore an exception to the slogan that in deontology the right is prior to the good. Although the basic human goods are the foundation for the moral rules, natural law theorists reject the consequentialist idea of maximizing the good: Because the basic human goods are incommensurable it is not possible to maximize the good. Proponents of natural law ethics typically adhere to moral absolutism and the principle of double effect. The best introductions to natural law ethics are Timmons 2013 and Gómez-Lobo 2002. A shorter survey is George and Tollefsen 2013. The most widely discussed proponents of natural law ethics are Joseph Boyle (1942–2016), John Finnis (b. 1940), and Germain Grisez (1929–2018). Finnis 2011 is one of the founding texts of this particular school of natural law ethics and is essential reading. A less wide-ranging book and more focused on ethics is Finnis 1983. Very helpful for understanding the relationship between natural law theory and consequentialism is the attack on consequentialism in Grisez 1991. Oderberg and Chappell 2004 contains new essays on various topics of natural law ethics. See also Absolutism.
Finnis, John. Natural Law and Natural Rights. 2d ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Same text as the first edition from 1980 except for a long new postscript. Very influential contemporary defense of natural law ethics, philosophy of law, and jurisprudence.
Find this resource:
Finnis, John. Fundamentals of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Shorter defense of Finnis’s natural law approach to ethics. Includes discussions of consequentialism and Kantian moral principles.
Find this resource:
George, Robert P., and Christopher Tollefsen. “Natural Law.” In The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Edited by Hugh LaFollette, 3519–3532. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Good general overview from two proponents of natural law theory.
Find this resource:
Gómez-Lobo, Alfonso. Morality and the Human Goods. An Introduction to Natural Law Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Clear and easy to read introduction. Explains the moral rules of natural law theory and shows how they are derived from a principle of practical rationality and a list of basic human goods. Later chapters apply the theory to abortion and euthanasia.
Find this resource:
Grisez, Germain. “Against Consequentialism.” In Natural Law. Vol. 2. Edited by John Finnis, 3–54. Aldershot, UK: Dartmouth, 1991.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First published 1978. Extensive critique of consequentialism from a prominent proponent of natural law ethics.
Find this resource:
Oderberg, David S., and Timothy Chappell, eds. Human Values. New Essays on Ethics and Natural Law. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Collection of eleven new articles on various topics of natural law ethics by philosophers sympathetic to or belonging to the natural law tradition.
Find this resource:
Timmons, Mark. “Natural Law Theory.” In Moral Theory: An Introduction. 2d ed. By Mark Timmons, 71–109. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Very good systematic introduction to natural law theory. Includes extensive discussion of absolutism and the principle of double effect which are essential elements of natural law theory.
Find this resource:
Contractualism
Contractualism is a major form of ethical deontology and explicitly devised by its main proponents, John Rawls and T. M. Scanlon, as an alternative to utilitarianism in political (Rawls) and moral philosophy (Scanlon). It is inspired by Kant’s ethics (and therefore sometimes discussed in the literature on Kantian ethics) and often contrasted with Hobbesian versions of contract theory (which are sometimes called “contractarianism”). The following citations are only include two classics of contractualism (Rawls 1999; Scanlon 1998), three overviews (Ashford and Mulgan 2018, Kumar 2010, Southwood 2009), and an article that deals at length with the claim that contractualism can justify deontological constraints (and solve the paradox of deontology). For a comprehensive guide to the literature see the Oxford Bibliographies articles in Philosophy “Moral Contractualism” and “John Rawls: Moral and Political Philosophy.”
Ashford, Elizabeth, and Tim Mulgan. “Contractualism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. 2018.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A very helpful introduction to Scanlonian contractualism. Particularly relevant on contractualism as a deontological theory are the sections “How Does Contractualism Differ from Utilitarianism?” and “How Does Contractualism Differ from Other Non-Consequentialist Ethical Theories?”
Find this resource:
Brand-Ballard, Jeffrey. “Contractualism and Deontic Restrictions.” Ethics 114 (2004): 369–400.
DOI: 10.1086/379354Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues against Hurley, Kumar, Ridge, and Scanlon that contractualism cannot support deontological constraints.
Find this resource:
Kumar, Rahul. “Contractualism.” In The Routledge Companion to Ethics. Edited by John Skorupski, 490–500. London: Routledge, 2010.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Brief overview of Scanlonian contractualism.
Find this resource:
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First edition published 1971. A classic in political philosophy, that has been very influential in moral philosophy, especially Rawls’s classification of moral theories in terms of how they relate the right to the good, his insistence on the priority of the right over the good, and his objection against utilitarianism that it ignores the separateness of persons.
Find this resource:
Scanlon, T. M. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The most significant and influential defense of moral contractualism. Contains a defense of deontological constraints based on the rejection of the teleological conception of values (and reasons) and an argument against utilitarian aggregation based on the idea that “the justifiability of a moral principle depends only on various individuals’ reasons for objecting to that principle and alternatives to it” (p. 229).
Find this resource:
Southwood, Nicholas. “Moral Contractualism.” Philosophy Compass 4 (2009): 926–937.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00256.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A brief, but very readable introduction to Scanlonian contractualism. It explains the key features of Scanlon’s contractualism (justifiability to others, reasonable rejectability, the individualist restriction, and mutual recognition) and discusses its appeal and five objections (duties to the cognitively limited and impaired, aggregation, demandingness, normativity, explanatory adequacy).
Find this resource:
Kantian Ethics
Kant’s ethics is widely regarded as the paradigm of deontological ethics. In many ethics textbooks the chapter on deontology is in fact a chapter on Kant’s ethics. Every Kant scholar, who endorses the main tenets of Kant’s theory (and does not adhere to their consequentialist interpretation; see Immanuel Kant—Deontological Versus Consequentialist Interpretations Of Kant’s Ethics) is a deontologist (although some do not like being called deontologists). Whoever wants to understand this kind of deontology has to study Kant’s ethics and should consult the Oxford Bibliographies article in Philosophy “Immanuel Kant: Ethics” for further literature on Kant’s ethics and its defenders. Listed in the following citations are only a few titles that convey the main ideas of Kant’s ethics and contemporary Kantian ethics without delving into Kant-exegesis. Baron 1997 gives a detailed account and defense of the distinctive features of Kantian ethics and compares them to consequentialism and virtue ethics. Ebels-Duggan 2011 argues that although most contemporary Kantians acknowledge the importance of values, especially the value of humanity, their conception of values and of the appropriate response to values differs decidedly from the consequentialist conception of value. Hill 2006 introduces to the different formulas of the Categorical Imperative and explores how they can be applied to duties of beneficence and mutual aid. Reath 2010 provides a brief overview of the distinctive features of contemporary Kantian ethics.
Baron, Marcia W. “Kantian Ethics.” In Three Methods of Ethics. By Marcia W. Baron, Philip Pettit, and Michael Slote, 3–91. Oxford: Blackwell, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A very readable presentation and defense of the distinctive features of Kantian ethics in contrast to consequentialism and virtue ethics.
Find this resource:
Ebels-Duggan, Kyla. “Kantian Ethics.” In The Continuum Companion to Ethics. Edited by Christian Miller, 168–189. London: Continuum, 2011.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Divides Kantians into Kantian constructivists, who want to derive substantive moral principles from formal principles of practical reasoning, and Kantian realists, who hold that substantive moral principles must be grounded in a substantive value, namely, humanity. Explains important differences between Kantian ethics and consequentialism, which hold even though most Kantians endorse the value of humanity and deny that in Kantian ethics the right is completely independent from considerations about value.
Find this resource:
Hill, Jr., Thomas E. “Kantian Normative Ethics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Edited by David Copp, 480–514. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Explains Kant’s formula of universal law, formula of humanity, formula of autonomy, and formula of the kingdom-of-ends and then illustrates how contemporary Kantians apply them to the duties of beneficence and mutual aid.
Find this resource:
Reath, Andrews. “Contemporary Kantian Ethics.” In The Routledge Companion to Ethics. Edited by John Skorupski, 456–466. London: Routledge, 2010.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Brief overview of contemporary Kantian approaches to the content of morality (treating persons as ends in themselves and never merely as a means; persons’ mutual respect for autonomy, which leads to a nonconsequentialist ideal of justifiability to others and to a liberal theory of justice), Kantian constructivism, and Kantian accounts of the authority of morality.
Find this resource:
Moral Pluralism
According to moral pluralism morality consists of a plurality of fundamental moral rules that cannot be derived from a supreme moral principle. Conflicts of rules in particular cases are possible and have to be resolved on a case-by-case basis. It stands in opposition to monistic deontological theories (like Kant’s) with one supreme moral principle, to particularist deontology (act-deontology) with no need for moral rules or principles, and to (Brad Hooker’s) rule-consequentialism with its claim to ground the plurality of moral rules in an overarching rule-consequentialist moral principle. The main charge against moral pluralism is that it is no genuine moral theory because the list of moral rules is arbitrary and lacks any unifying and explanatory rationale. Gaut 1993 and Gaut 1999 defends moral pluralism against common objections and develops in Gaut 2002, a nonintuitionist justification of moral pluralism. McNaughton 2002 defends Rossian pluralism against the common charge that it is only an unjustified, arbitrary list of duties that cannot guide us in resolving moral conflicts. Ross 2002 (Chapter 2) is the point of reference for all subsequent discussions of pluralism. Stratton-Lake 2011 argues that a pluralist moral theory offers a more unified account of our moral reasons than a monist deontological or consequentialist moral theory. Timmons 2013 offers the best introduction to Ross’s pluralism. Audi 2004 is an ambitious novel intuitionistic theory that grounds ten Rossian middle-level principles in Kant’s formula of humanity and a pluralistic theory of value. See also British Intuitionists—Secondary Literature on Ross.
Audi, Robert. The Good in the Right. A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this very ambitious and important book Audi develops a “value-based Kantian intuitionism,” which combines the best of Ross and Kant: Audi begins with a new defense and interpretation of intuitionism and then employs Kant’s formula of humanity to select, explain, justify, and resolve conflicts between ten “middle-level” Rossian prima facie principles (listed and explained on pp. 188–95).
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. “Moral Pluralism.” Philosophical Papers 22 (1993): 17–40.
DOI: 10.1080/05568649309506391Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Contains a defense of moral pluralism against various objections (from John Rawls, David Brink, and Jonathan Dancy) and an argument for a pluralist common-sense morality.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. “Rag-bags, Disputes and Moral Pluralism.” Utilitas 11 (1999): 37–48.
DOI: 10.1017/S0953820800002259Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A defense of moral pluralism against objections from (the rule consequentialist) Brad Hooker.
Find this resource:
Gaut, Berys. “Justifying Moral Pluralism.” In Ethical Intuitionism. Re-Evaluations. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake, 137–160. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Defends Ross’s moral pluralism but thinks that his intuitionist justification has to be abandoned in favor of a value-grounded “experiential foundationalism.”
Find this resource:
McNaughton, David. “An Unconnected Heap of Duties?” In Ethical Intuitionism. Re-Evaluations. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake, 76–91. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First published 1996. Argues that Rossian pluralism is not an arbitrary list of unconnected duties but a list of the most general underivative “fundamental morally relevant characteristics of actions,” which has no less a claim to systematizing our common-sense morality than consequentialism. McNaughton admits that Ross’s list of basic duties cannot guide us in solving difficult moral problems but thinks that no moral theory can help us in this regard.
Find this resource:
Ross, W. D. The Right and the Good. Edited by Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002.
DOI: 10.1093/0199252653.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Originally published 1930. In Chapter 2, the locus classicus of moral pluralism, Ross introduces his famous list of prima facie duties.
Find this resource:
Stratton-Lake, Philip. “Recalcitrant Pluralism.” Ratio 24 (2011): 364–383.
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9329.2011.00507.xSave Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Argues that Rossian pluralism is the best form of deontology and gives a better account of moral reasons than indirect consequentialism. Each of the Rossian principles picks out facts that give us four reasons: (explanatory) reasons why we morally ought to do certain acts, (normative) moral reasons we have to do them, (motivational) reasons why good people will do them, and a (normative) reason to resent our failure to do what we ought.
Find this resource:
Timmons, Mark. “Moral Pluralism.” In Moral Theory. An Introduction. 2d ed. By Mark Timmons, 245–269. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2013.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A very clear, sympathetic presentation and evaluation of Ross’s moral pluralism, with an annotated guide to further reading.
Find this resource:
Further Forms of Deontology
Listed here are some major works that do not fit easily into the other categories of deontology. Dancy 1993 defends a particularist deontology (formerly called act-deontology). Darwall 2006 presents a new foundation for a contractualist deontology based on what he calls second-personal reasons. Donagan 1977 and Gewirth 1978 are two Kant-inspired forms of deontology: Donagan 1977 wants to justify Hebrew-Christian absolutism on the basis of respect for persons, derived from his interpretation of Kant’s formula of humanity. Gewirth 1978 adopts Kant’s ethical rationalism and derives a supreme principle of morality from the necessary conditions of human actions. Gert 2004 and Gert 2005 defend an approach (especially popular in applied ethics) the author calls “common morality.”
Dancy, Jonathan. Moral Reasons. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Sophisticated defense of moral particularism, which corresponds to what has earlier been called act-deontology. Mounts impressive arguments against Ross’s (generalist) idea of prima facie duties. In Chapters 10 to 13 Dancy discusses different conceptions of agent-relativity and defends agent-relative options and constraints against consequentialism.
Find this resource:
Darwall, Stephen. The Second-Person Standpoint. Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this important and ambitious book, Darwall presents a new justification of morality, which lays the foundation for a contractualist deontological theory. Central to this approach are second-personal reasons whose validity depend “on presupposed authority and accountability relations between persons” (p. 8). Since moral obligations are grounded in second-personal reasons and second-personal reasons are fundamentally agent-relative; the second-person standpoint can provide a rationale for (agent-relative) deontological constraints.
Find this resource:
Donagan, Alan. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A Kantian (near absolutist) moral theory (and defense of Hebrew-Christian morality) based on Donagan’s interpretation of Kant’s formula of humanity as “it is impermissible not to respect every human being, oneself or any other, as a rational creature” (p. 66).
Find this resource:
Gert, Bernard. Common Morality. Deciding What to Do. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
DOI: 10.1093/0195173716.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A shorter, more accessible version of Gert 2005.
Find this resource:
Gert, Bernard. Morality: Its Nature and Justification. Rev ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
DOI: 10.1093/0195176898.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Gert’s approach consists of a description and justification of “common morality.” Its main components are ten moral rules and a procedure for determining justified violations of the moral rules (based on a specification of morally relevant features). According to Gert, his theory has affinities to many standard moral theories (especially to rule-consequentialism and Rossian pluralism) but is best described as a “natural law theory in the tradition of Hobbes” (p. xiii).
Find this resource:
Gewirth, Alan. Reason and Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this paradigm of Kantian ethical rationalism Gewirth argues that the necessary conditions of actions (”the generic features of action”) compel every agent (on pain of self-contradiction) to accept that “all prospective purposive agents have rights to freedom and well-being” (p. 48) and to accept as the supreme principle of morality the “principle of generic consistency”: “Act in accord with the generic rights of your recipients as well as of yourself.” (p. 135)
Find this resource:
Deontology in Applied Ethics
Deontology in its various forms has, of course, made many important contributions to applied ethics, some examples of which are listed here. Altman 2011 shows the usefulness of Kant’s ethics to some topics in applied ethics. Beauchamp and Childress 2009 and Gert, et al. 2006 both defend a “common morality” approach to biomedical ethics, based, respectively, on four moral principles and ten moral rules. Kamm 2013 applies the author’s method of eliciting our moral intuitions through extensive use of lots of slightly modified hypothetical examples. Oderberg 2000 and some authors in Oderberg and Laing 1997 defend a natural law approach to applied ethics. Regan 1983 uses a rights based view to argue for animal rights.
Altman, Matthew C. Kant and Applied Ethics: The Uses and Limits of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011.
DOI: 10.1002/9781118114162Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This in-depth analysis of the value of Kant’s ethics to applied ethics demonstrates that Kant’s ethics can make important contributions to many topics in applied ethics (such as animal ethics, environmental ethics, health care, patient autonomy, physician-assisted suicide, refusing life-saving treatment, organ donation, death penalty, and same-sex marriage) but is of limited use in other areas (e.g., the abortion debate and business ethics).
Find this resource:
Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 6th ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
First edition 1979. In this book—the most influential book in biomedical ethics—the authors present their four-principles approach (also called “principlism”) and argue that biomedical ethics should proceed by applying the principles of autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice. These principles are rooted in our “common morality” and cannot be derived from an overarching supreme principle but allow the derivation of more specific moral rules.
Find this resource:
Gert, Bernard, Charles M. Culver, and K. Danner Clouser. Bioethics: A Systematic Approach. 2d ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
DOI: 10.1093/0195159063.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
The authors defend their “common morality” approach to bioethics (and morality in general), contrast it with Beauchamp/Childress’s principlism and apply it to various topics in medical ethics (e.g., death, euthanasia, informed consent, malady, mental maladies, and paternalism). Essential to their approach are ten moral rules and a procedure for determining justified violations of these rules.
Find this resource:
Kamm, F. M. Bioethical Prescriptions: To Create, End, Choose, and Improve Lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199971985.001.0001Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
A collection of twenty-seven essays by one of the foremost defenders of deontology. The essays cover a wide range of topics grouped under the headings “Death and Dying,” “Early Life,” “Genetic and Other Enhancements,” “Allocating Scarce Resources,” and “Methodology.”
Find this resource:
Oderberg, David. Applied Ethics: A Non-Consequentialist Approach. Oxford: Blackwell, 2000.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
Treatment of abortion, euthanasia, animal ethics, capital punishment, and war from a fierce anti-consequentialist point of view.
Find this resource:
Oderberg, David S., and Jacqueline A. Laing, eds. Human Lives: Critical Essays on Consequentialist Bioethics. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1997.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
This collection, aimed to challenge the dominance of consequentialism in bioethics, contains twelve newly written articles on various bioethical topics (e.g., speciesism) from a deontological point of view.
Find this resource:
Regan, Tom. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1983.
Save Citation »Export Citation » Share Citation »
In this classic Regan compares different ethical theories and defends the “rights view” as the best theory all things considered.
Find this resource:
Article
- A Priori Knowledge
- Abduction and Explanatory Reasoning
- Ability
- Abortion
- Abstract Objects
- Action
- Addams, Jane
- Adorno, Theodor
- Aesthetic Hedonism
- Aesthetics, Analytic Approaches to
- Aesthetics, Continental
- Aesthetics, Environmental
- Aesthetics, History of
- African Philosophy, Contemporary
- Alexander, Samuel
- Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
- Anarchism, Philosophical
- Animal Rights
- Anscombe, G. E. M.
- Anthropic Principle, The
- Applied Ethics
- Aquinas, Thomas
- Argument Mapping
- Art and Emotion
- Art and Knowledge
- Art and Morality
- Artifacts
- Assertion
- Astell, Mary
- Atheism
- Augustine
- Aurelius, Marcus
- Austin, J. L.
- Autonomy
- Bacon, Francis
- Bayesianism
- Beauty
- Belief
- Bergson, Henri
- Berkeley, George
- Biology, Philosophy of
- Bolzano, Bernard
- Boredom, Philosophy of
- British Idealism
- Buber, Martin
- Buddhist Philosophy
- Burge, Tyler
- Business Ethics
- Camus, Albert
- Canterbury, Anselm of
- Carnap, Rudolf
- Causation
- Cavendish, Margaret
- Certainty
- Chemistry, Philosophy of
- Childhood, Philosophy of
- Chinese Philosophy
- Cognitive Ability
- Cognitive Phenomenology
- Cognitive Science, Philosophy of
- Coherentism
- Color
- Communitarianism
- Computational Science
- Computer Science, Philosophy of
- Comte, Auguste
- Concepts
- Conceptual Role Semantics
- Conditionals
- Confirmation
- Confucius
- Connectionism
- Consciousness
- Constructive Empiricism
- Contemporary Hylomorphism
- Contextualism
- Contrastivism
- Cook Wilson, John
- Cosmology, Philosophy of
- Critical Theory
- Culture and Cognition
- Daoism and Philosophy
- Davidson, Donald
- de Beauvoir, Simone
- de Montaigne, Michel
- Death
- Decision Theory
- Deleuze, Gilles
- Democracy
- Depiction
- Derrida, Jacques
- Descartes, René
- Descartes, René: Sensory Representations
- Descriptions
- Dewey, John
- Dialetheism
- Disability
- Disagreement, Epistemology of
- Disjunctivism
- Dispositions
- Doing and Allowing
- du Châtelet, Emilie
- Dummett, Michael
- Dutch Book Arguments
- Early Modern Philosophy, 1600-1750
- Eastern Orthodox Philosophical Thought
- Education, Philosophy of
- Emotion
- Engineering, Philosophy and Ethics of
- Environmental Philosophy
- Epicurus
- Epistemic Basing Relation
- Epistemic Defeat
- Epistemic Injustice
- Epistemic Justification
- Epistemic Philosophy of Logic
- Epistemology
- Epistemology and Active Externalism
- Epistemology, Bayesian
- Epistemology, Feminist
- Epistemology, Internalism and Externalism in
- Epistemology, Moral
- Epistemology of Education
- Ethical Consequentialism
- Ethical Deontology
- Ethical Intuitionism
- Eugenics and Philosophy
- Events, The Philosophy of
- Evidence
- Evidence-Based Medicine, Philosophy of
- Evidential Support Relation In Epistemology, The
- Evil
- Evolutionary Debunking Arguments in Ethics
- Evolutionary Epistemology
- Experimental Philosophy
- Explanations of Religion
- Extended Mind Thesis, The
- Externalism and Internalism in the Philosophy of Mind
- Faith, Conceptions of
- Fatalism
- Feminist Philosophy
- Feyerabend, Paul
- Fichte, Johann Gottlieb
- Fiction
- Fictionalism
- Fictionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Film, Philosophy of
- Foot, Philippa
- Foreknowledge
- Forgiveness
- Formal Epistemology
- Foucault, Michel
- Free Will
- Frege, Gottlob
- Gadamer, Hans-Georg
- Geometry, Epistemology of
- God and Possible Worlds
- God, Arguments for the Existence of
- God, The Existence and Attributes of
- Grice, Paul
- Habermas, Jürgen
- Hart, H. L. A.
- Heaven and Hell
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Aesthetics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Metaphysics
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of History
- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Philosophy of Politics
- Heidegger, Martin: Early Works
- Hermeneutics
- Higher Education, Philosophy of
- History, Philosophy of
- Hobbes, Thomas
- Horkheimer, Max
- Human Rights
- Hume, David: Aesthetics
- Hume, David: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Husserl, Edmund
- Idealizations in Science
- Identity in Physics
- Images
- Imagination
- Imagination and Belief
- Impossible Worlds
- Incommensurability in Science
- Indian Philosophy
- Indispensability of Mathematics
- Inductive Reasoning
- Infinitism
- Instruments in Science
- Intellectual Humility
- Intentionality, Collective
- Intuitions
- James, William
- Japanese Philosophy
- Kant and the Laws of Nature
- Kant, Immanuel: Aesthetics and Teleology
- Kant, Immanuel: Ethics
- Kant, Immanuel: Theoretical Philosophy
- Kierkegaard, Søren
- Knowledge
- Knowledge-first Epistemology
- Knowledge-How
- Kuhn, Thomas S.
- Lacan, Jacques
- Lakatos, Imre
- Langer, Susanne
- Language of Thought
- Language, Philosophy of
- Latin American Philosophy
- Laws of Nature
- Legal Epistemology
- Legal Philosophy
- Legal Positivism
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm
- Levinas, Emmanuel
- Lewis, C. I.
- Liberty
- Literature, Philosophy of
- Locke, John
- Locke, John: Identity, Persons, and Personal Identity
- Logic
- Lottery and Preface Paradoxes, The
- Lucretius
- Machiavelli, Niccolò
- Martin Heidegger: Later Works
- Martin Heidegger: Middle Works
- Marx, Karl
- Material Constitution
- Mathematical Explanation
- Mathematical Pluralism
- Mathematical Structuralism
- Mathematics, Ontology of
- Mathematics, Philosophy of
- Mathematics, Visual Thinking in
- McDowell, John
- McTaggart, John
- Meaning of Life, The
- Mechanisms in Science
- Medically Assisted Dying
- Medicine, Contemporary Philosophy of
- Medieval Logic
- Medieval Philosophy
- Memory
- Mental Causation
- Mereology
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice
- Meta-epistemological Skepticism
- Metaepistemology
- Metaethics
- Metametaphysics
- Metaphilosophy
- Metaphor
- Metaphysical Grounding
- Metaphysics, Contemporary
- Metaphysics, Feminist
- Midgley, Mary
- Mill, John Stuart
- Mind, Metaphysics of
- Modal Epistemology
- Modality
- Models and Theories in Science
- Modularity
- Montesquieu
- Moore, G. E.
- Moral Contractualism
- Moral Naturalism and Nonnaturalism
- Moral Responsibility
- Multiculturalism
- Murdoch, Iris
- Music, Analytic Philosophy of
- Nationalism
- Natural Kinds
- Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics
- Naïve Realism
- Neo-Confucianism
- Neuroscience, Philosophy of
- Nietzsche, Friedrich
- Nonexistent Objects
- Normative Ethics
- Normative Foundations, Philosophy of Law:
- Normativity and Social Explanation
- Objectivity
- Occasionalism
- Olfaction
- Ontological Dependence
- Ontology of Art
- Ordinary Objects
- Other Minds
- Pacifism
- Pain
- Panpsychism
- Paradoxes
- Particularism in Ethics
- Pascal, Blaise
- Paternalism
- Patriotism
- Peirce, Charles Sanders
- Perception, Cognition, Action
- Perception, The Problem of
- Perfectionism
- Persistence
- Personal Identity
- Phenomenal Concepts
- Phenomenal Conservatism
- Phenomenology
- Philosophy for Children
- Photography, Analytic Philosophy of
- Physicalism
- Physicalism and Metaphysical Naturalism
- Physics, Experiments in
- Plato
- Plotinus
- Political Epistemology
- Political Obligation
- Political Philosophy
- Popper, Karl
- Pornography and Objectification, Analytic Approaches to
- Practical Knowledge
- Practical Moral Skepticism
- Practical Reason
- Pragmatics
- Pragmatism
- Probabilistic Representations of Belief
- Probability, Interpretations of
- Problem of Divine Hiddenness, The
- Problem of Evil, The
- Propositions
- Psychology, Philosophy of
- Punishment
- Pyrrhonism
- Qualia
- Quietism
- Quine, W. V. O.
- Race
- Racist Jokes
- Rationalism
- Rationality
- Rawls, John: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Realism and Anti-Realism
- Realization
- Reasons in Epistemology
- Reductionism in Biology
- Reference, Theory of
- Reid, Thomas
- Relativism
- Reliabilism
- Religion, Philosophy of
- Religious Belief, Epistemology of
- Religious Experience
- Religious Pluralism
- Ricoeur, Paul
- Rights
- Risk, Philosophy of
- Rorty, Richard
- Rousseau, Jean-Jacques
- Rule-Following
- Russell, Bertrand
- Ryle, Gilbert
- Sartre, Jean-Paul
- Schopenhauer, Arthur
- Science and Religion
- Science, Theoretical Virtues in
- Scientific Explanation
- Scientific Progress
- Scientific Realism
- Scientific Representation
- Scientific Revolutions
- Scotus, Duns
- Self-Knowledge
- Sellars, Wilfrid
- Semantic Externalism
- Semantic Minimalism
- Semiotics
- Seneca
- Senses, The
- Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology
- Singular Thought
- Situated Cognition
- Situationism and Virtue Theory
- Skepticism, Contemporary
- Skepticism, History of
- Slurs, Pejoratives, and Hate Speech
- Smith, Adam: Moral and Political Philosophy
- Social Aspects of Scientific Knowledge
- Social Epistemology
- Social Identity
- Sounds and Auditory Perception
- Space and Time
- Speech Acts
- Spinoza, Baruch
- Stebbing, Susan
- Strawson, P. F.
- Structural Realism
- Suicide
- Supererogation
- Supervenience
- Tarski, Alfred
- Technology, Philosophy of
- Testimony, Epistemology of
- Theoretical Terms in Science
- Thomas Aquinas' Philosophy of Religion
- Thought Experiments
- Time and Tense
- Time Travel
- Toleration
- Torture
- Transcendental Arguments
- Tropes
- Trust
- Truth
- Truth and the Aim of Belief
- Truthmaking
- Turing Test
- Two-Dimensional Semantics
- Understanding
- Uniqueness and Permissiveness in Epistemology
- Utilitarianism
- Vagueness
- Value of Knowledge
- Vienna Circle
- Virtue Epistemology
- Virtue Ethics
- Virtues, Epistemic
- Virtues, Intellectual
- Voluntarism, Doxastic
- War
- Weakness of Will
- Weil, Simone
- Well-Being
- William of Ockham
- Williams, Bernard
- Wisdom
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Early Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Later Works
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig: Middle Works
- Wollstonecraft, Mary